Difference between revisions of "Book/The Medium-Specific Narrative"

From Conceptual Reconstructionism Project
 
(12 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
==Interpretation of the “medium-specific narrative”==
{{Book Part}}


The alternative to the interpretation of the average value is what, in the absence of a more marketable expression, I call the “interpretation of the medium-specific narrative.” The medium-specific narratives are the opposite of the mosaics. Instead of a loose whole, one searches for some tightly-knit cognitive structure, with all extras removed. A work contains many medium-specific narratives that may overlap. There may not even be a “the one” medium-specific narrative that the creator is supposed to have designed, intended, and wanted for their audience. The existence of “the one” is best left to speculative (and ultimately sterile) endeavours. Some narrative may look like it, but in general, the medium-specific narratives are modest in scope and fundamentally hedonistic: the joy comes from finding one that is satisfying enough in a purely subjective sense.
==Interpretation of the medium-specific narrative==


The expression “interpretation of '''the''' medium-specific narrative” (non-plural) as used in this essay is somewhat misleading. It actually means an interpretation that reveals one of the medium-specific narratives of the interpreted content. You can think of “[b]the[/b] medium-specific narrative” as the content itself, and the “interpretation” as a medium-specific sub-narrative that results from a focused abstraction of “'''the''' medium-specifc narrative”.
The alternative to the interpretation of the average value is what, in the absence of a more marketable expression, I call the “interpretation of the medium-specific narrative.” The medium-specific narratives are the opposite of the mosaics. Instead of a loose whole, one searches for some tightly-knit structure, with all extras removed. A work contains many medium-specific narratives that may overlap. There may not even be a “the one” medium-specific narrative that the creator is supposed to have designed and intended for their audience. The existence of “the one” is best left to speculative (and ultimately sterile) endeavours. Some narrative may look like it, but in general, the medium-specific narratives are modest in scope and fundamentally hedonistic: the satisfaction of finding one is purely subjective.


===The medium-specific narrative as a narrative of elements related to each other due to the nature of the medium. The interpretation of the average value as a narrative of disparate elements. Proximity of the medium-specific narrative to the content as a timeline of events that actually happen to the consumer. The interpretation of the medium-specific narrative is essentially the rendering of the interpreted content as a medium-specific narrative, with an implicit non-committal value judgment that doesn’t detract from objectivity.===
The expression “interpretation of '''the''' medium-specific narrative” (non-plural) as used in this essay is somewhat misleading. It actually means an interpretation that reveals one of the medium-specific narratives of the interpreted content. You can think of “'''the''' medium-specific narrative” as the content itself, and the “interpretation” as a medium-specific sub-narrative that results from a filtering of “'''the''' medium-specifc narrative”.


Narrative interpretation is an endeavor to view a work as, broadly speaking, a “story,” i.e., every element in the work is viewed in light of previous elements, the '''premises'''. If the elements form a succession of events in the same timeline, characters, locations, etc., then we recognize the traditional concept of story. But if the elements are the regions of a painting or the motifs of a musical piece, the concepts of “story” and “premise” take on a peculiar quality '''relative to the nature of the medium'''. In a pop song, an element could be a section, for example the chorus, and its premise could be the verse. Depending on the merits of doing so, one could look at a more granular level where an element could mean a phrase, the segment of a phrase, or even a note. Such an element can become the premise to an element that follows it in the song. In a painting, an “element” could, for example, mean a painted region, an object, or a motif. The concept of “premise” here can be somewhat misleading, as there isn’t always a declared timeline. In this case, I like to generalize the definition of “premise” to mean “another element of the painting” which gives it context. The elements of a painting implicitly bond together through an implicit timeline, which is the timeline of the viewing experience. The movement of the viewer’s gaze from one region of the painting to another creates a subjective timeline of perceptions, a “story” of perceptions. This timeline tends to be ignored because the observer tends to compress it during the cognitive process—e.g., when we see a portrait, we recognize the face almost instantaneously, without going over the facial features individually. We’ll later see how this “photographic memory” can prejudice visual media.
===The medium-specific narrative as a narrative of elements related to each other due to the nature of the medium. The interpretation of the average value as a juxtaposition of disparate elements. Proximity of the medium-specific narrative to the content as a timeline of events that actually happen to the consumer. The interpretation of the medium-specific narrative is essentially a rendering of a medium-specific narrative, with an implicit non-committal value judgment that doesn’t detract from objectivity.===


Note that the physical frame of the narrative (the canvas, the page, or the sound track) is a convention. It narrows the search for narratives. But you could imagine looking for (and finding) medium-specific narratives in Nature or in any unintended arrangement of objects. This has important ramifications for how one looks at conventional art. The focus is now on the perceptions '''as they happen to the observer, not as they are intended by some intelligent being'''. In fact, the medium-specific narratives don’t refer to an external intelligent being at all, since it is outside the medium. On the other hand, a mosaic is the result when one talks of such an intelligent being, a Creator or Artist, in relation to the work.
Narrative interpretation is an endeavor to view a work as, broadly speaking, a “story,” i.e., every element in the work is viewed in light of previous elements, the '''premises''' or '''context'''. If the elements form a succession of events in the same timeline, characters, locations, etc., then we recognize the traditional concept of story. But if the elements are the regions of a painting or the motifs of a musical piece, the concepts of “story” and “premise” take on a peculiar quality '''relative to the nature of the medium'''. In a pop song, an element could be a section, for example the chorus, and its premise could be the verse. Depending on the merits of doing so, one could look at a more granular level where an element could mean a phrase, the segment of a phrase, or even a note. Such an element can be seen as the premise to any other element that follows it in the song. In a painting, an “element” could, for example, mean a painted region, an object, or a motif. The concept of “premise” here can be somewhat misleading, as there isn’t a declared timeline. In this case, I like to generalize the definition of “premise” to mean “another element of the painting” which both gives it context and is given a context by it, depending on which element you view as the premise. The elements of a painting implicitly bond together through an implicit timeline, which is the timeline of the viewing experience. The movement of the viewer’s gaze from one region of the painting to another creates a subjective timeline of perceptions, a “story” of perceptions. This timeline tends to be ignored because the observer tends to compress it during the cognitive process—e.g., when we see a portrait, we recognize the face almost instantaneously, without going over the facial features individually. We’ll later see how this “photographic memory” can prejudice visual media.


The “medium specificity” of the narrative means that the elements of the narrative stay homogeneous with respect to each other as parts of the same medium, in the sense that they relate to each other as parts of a narrative. In other words, the narrative stays '''intra-medium'''. Intuitively, it interprets the whole work as the self-contained unit, in a way that frames the content as events happening on a closed timeline of perceptions (not the timeline of a story in the traditional sense). As a medium-specific narrative, a song is a succession of perception-elements that occur to the listener (melodies, harmonies, notes, and so on) and nothing else. By contrast, the interpretation of the average value results in a mosaic of features, including mood, theme, genre, and so on. Therefore, the listener first experiences the elements of medium-specific narratives. Considerations like theme or genre are high-level interpretations of these elements.
The physical frame of the narrative (the canvas, the pages, or the sound track) is a convention. It narrows the search for narratives. But you could imagine looking for (and finding) medium-specific narratives in Nature or in any unintended arrangement of objects. This has important ramifications for how one looks at conventional art. The focus is now on the perceptions '''as they happen to the observer, not as they are intended by some intelligent being'''. In fact, the medium-specific narratives don’t refer to an external intelligent being at all, since it is outside the medium. On the other hand, a mosaic is the result when one talks of such an intelligent being, a Creator or Artist, in relation to the work.
 
The “medium specificity” of the narrative means that the elements of the narrative are homogeneous parts of the same medium. In other words, the narrative stays '''intra-medium'''. It is an interpretation of a content as a self-contained unit, filtering perceptions happening on a closed timeline (not the timeline of a story in the traditional sense). As a medium-specific narrative, a song is a succession of perceptions (melodies, harmonies, notes, and so on) and nothing else. By contrast, the interpretation of the average value results in a mosaic of features, including mood, theme, genre, and so on. Therefore, the listener first experiences the elements of medium-specific narratives. Considerations like theme or genre are high-level interpretations of these elements.


===The mosaic as the medium-specific narrative of reviews===
===The mosaic as the medium-specific narrative of reviews===
Line 17: Line 19:
The interpretation of the average value reveals itself when one begins to analyze reviews, and more particularly their narrative structure (or rather the lack thereof), rather than just their supposed usefulness. In a way, reviews are works about works, using a stylistically distinctive thought process that builds upon content through an amnesic process. As such, the reviews have their own medium-specific narratives, of which the mosaic is the invariant. We saw an example through the interpretation of a modern art review.
The interpretation of the average value reveals itself when one begins to analyze reviews, and more particularly their narrative structure (or rather the lack thereof), rather than just their supposed usefulness. In a way, reviews are works about works, using a stylistically distinctive thought process that builds upon content through an amnesic process. As such, the reviews have their own medium-specific narratives, of which the mosaic is the invariant. We saw an example through the interpretation of a modern art review.


Medium-specific narratives are therefore not confined to art. In terms of methodology, their interpretation doesn’t make any distinction between art and science, between fiction and non-fiction, between review and reviewed content. In fact, most critiques and analyses you will find in this text are interpretations of the medium-specific narratives of various papers, books, discourses, reviews, and everyday chatter. The interpretations are presented rather informally for the ease of reading, while staying recognizable by the characteristic minuteness with which they capture medium-specific intricacies.
More generally, medium-specific narratives are not confined to art. In terms of methodology, their interpretation doesn’t make any distinction between art and science, between fiction and non-fiction, between review and reviewed content. In fact, most critiques and analyses you will find in this text are interpretations of the medium-specific narratives of various papers, books, discourses, reviews, and everyday chatter. The interpretations are presented rather informally for the ease of reading, while staying recognizable by the characteristic minuteness with which they capture medium-specific intricacies.


===A medium-specific narrative from John Keats’ ''Ode on a Grecian Urn''. Interpretation styles versus self-reliance of the medium-specific narrative===
===A medium-specific narrative from John Keats’ ''Ode on a Grecian Urn''. Interpretation writing styles===


I chose John Keats’ ''Ode on a Grecian Urn'' because it is short and well-established in academic circles.
I chose John Keats’ ''Ode on a Grecian Urn'' because it is short and well-established in academic circles.
Line 78: Line 80:
Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.”||John Keats|''Ode on a Grecian Urn''}}</div>
Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.”||John Keats|''Ode on a Grecian Urn''}}</div>


When I look for a medium-specific narrative, I try to find one that roughly covers the whole work. In logical terms, one that justifies the work as a unit. Here’s one:
When I look for a medium-specific narrative, I try to find one that roughly covers the whole work, one that justifies the work as a unit. Here’s one:


# The narrator questions a silent “thou.”
# The narrator questions a silent “thou.”
# The narrator associates the silent (“those unheard are sweeter”) with the eternal (“canst not leave […] nor ever,” “never, never”, “For ever,” etc.).
# The narrator associates the silent (“those unheard are sweeter”) with the eternal (“canst not leave […] nor ever,” “never, never”, “For ever,” etc.).
# The eternal is then associated with successions of “happy” and “love” (“Ah, happy, happy boughs!”, “happy melodist”, “More happy love! more happy, happy love!”).
# The eternal is then associated with repetitions of “happy” framed between assonant words (“Ah, '''happy, happy''' boughs!”, “More happy love! more '''happy, happy''' love!”).
# Finally, when the eternally silent (“Thou, '''silent''' form, dost tease us out of thought as doth '''eternity'''”) says something, it addresses the narrator’s questioning (“all '''ye need to know'''”) through structures of succession, reminiscent of the narrator’s successions of “happy:“'''Beauty is truth, truth beauty''', that is all '''ye know''' on earth, and all '''ye need to know'''.”
# Finally, when the eternally silent (“Thou, '''silent''' form, dost tease us out of thought as doth '''eternity'''”) says something, it addresses the narrator’s questioning (“all '''ye need to know'''”) through structures of repetiton, reminiscent of the framed repetitions of “happy”: “'''Beauty is truth, truth beauty''', that is '''all ye know''' on earth, and '''all ye need to know'''.”


All the terms of the interpretations are reused and combined in different contexts. In (1), the “silent thou” is asked questions which are addressed in (4). The repetitions of the answer “beauty is truth, truth beauty” echo the repetitions of the words happy and love in (3), but in a non-silent context which contrasts the silence in (1) and (2). A narrative thus emerges.
All the terms of the interpretations are reused and combined in different contexts. In (1), the “silent thou” is asked questions which are addressed in (4). The repetitions of the answer “beauty is truth, truth beauty” echo the repetitions of the words happy and love in (3), but in a non-silent context which contrasts the silence in (1) and (2). A narrative thus emerges.
Line 89: Line 91:
This narrative is medium-specific in the sense that it takes elements directly from the poem with almost no recourse to subjective interpretation. I say almost, because there is certainly some layer of interpretation there. I did skip many details, even entire parts of the poem. I also didn’t mention the stanza structure or the rhyme schemes. Implicit in these oversights is an assessment that they weren’t needed in the narrative I wanted to highlight. If you study the stanza structure or the poem’s themes, as most scholars do, you get invariants rather than a narrative. But this choice, to prefer this poem-wide narrative over invariants, is already an act of subjective interpretation, even if, in the last analysis, I just highlighted certain passages of the poem and their relationships.
This narrative is medium-specific in the sense that it takes elements directly from the poem with almost no recourse to subjective interpretation. I say almost, because there is certainly some layer of interpretation there. I did skip many details, even entire parts of the poem. I also didn’t mention the stanza structure or the rhyme schemes. Implicit in these oversights is an assessment that they weren’t needed in the narrative I wanted to highlight. If you study the stanza structure or the poem’s themes, as most scholars do, you get invariants rather than a narrative. But this choice, to prefer this poem-wide narrative over invariants, is already an act of subjective interpretation, even if, in the last analysis, I just highlighted certain passages of the poem and their relationships.


I could cook the interpretation a little bit, because it is a little too raw as it is. I could add some commentary that would express the feelings and value judgments that led me to this narrative. I could say this:
I could cook the interpretation a little bit, as it is a little too raw as it is. I could add some commentary that would express the feelings and value judgments that led me to this narrative. I could say this:
 
{{c|John Keats thus makes us realize that our questionings are superfluous, in the sense that the answer was already implied in the narrator’s enthusiastic exuberance. The answer is in the rythmic expressivity—whether in the questioning itself (the series of “what”) or in the insistence on eternity, happiness and love—that seems to anticipate T.S. Eliot’s criticism of the “grammatically meaningless” statement that “beauty is truth, truth beauty.”}}
 
I will usually choose to stay away from this style of '''writing''', but this is a purely personal choice. I personally like to address an audience that doesn’t need to be spoon-fed and will arrive at its own conclusions. In fact, I would argue that the raw interpretation doesn’t need any conclusion. The elements of the narrative are interlinked with one another in such a way that the whole point is lost as soon as one tries to wrap things up in a generic conclusion—i.e., the narrative is self-contained and self-conclusive, somewhat like “beauty is truth, truth beauty” is self-contained and self-conclusive. In fact, any type of value-based conclusion would attract the sort of (rightful) criticism against awkward attempts at penetrating non-objective concepts through objective interpretation—cf. Derrida’s criticism of Jean Rousset who tried to describe passion in literature (or at least invite his readers to sense it) using only geometrical concepts like “rings,” “symmetry,” “helices,” and so on:
 
{{quote|At the start of the essay ''Polyeucte or The Ring and the Helix'', the author cautiously warns us that, if he insists upon “schemas that might seem excessively geometrical, it’s because Corneille, more than any other, practiced symmetries.” Moreover “this geometry is not cultivated for itself,” “it is in the great plays a means subordinated to passionate ends.”


{{c|John Keats thus makes us realize that our questionings are superfluous, in the sense that the answer was already implied in the narrator’s enthusiastic exuberance. The answer is in the rythmic expressivity—whether in the questioning itself (the series of “what”) or in the insistence on eternity, happiness and love—that almost seems to anticipate T.S. Eliot’s criticism of the “grammatically meaningless” statement that “beauty is truth, truth beauty.”}}
But what does this essay actually tell us? Only the geometry of a theater which is, however, “that of the mad passion, of the heroic enthusiasm.” Not only does the geometrical structure of ''Polyeucte'' mobilize all the resources and attention of the author, but the whole teleology of Corneille’s trajectory is attached to it.
|Au début de l’essai intitulé ''Polyeucte ou la bouche et la vrille'', l’auteur prévient prudemment que, s’il insiste sur “des schèmes qui peuvent paraître excessivement géométriques, c’est que Corneille, plus que tout autre, a a pratiqué les symétrie”. De plus “cette géométrie n’est pas cultivée pour elle-même”, “elle est dans les grandes pièces un moyen subordonné à des fins passionnelles”.


I will usually choose to stay away from this style of interpretation, but this is a purely personal choice. I personally like to address an audience that doesn’t need to be spoon-fed and will arrive at its own conclusions. In fact, I would argue that the raw interpretation doesn’t need any conclusion. The elements of the narrative are interlinked with one another in such a way that the whole point is lost as soon as one tries to wrap things up in a generic conclusion—i.e., the narrative is self-contained and self-conclusive.
Mais que nous livre en fait cet essai? La seule géométrie d’un théâtre qui est pourtant “celui de la passion folle, de l’enthousiasme héroïque”. Non seulement la structure géométrique de ''Polyeucte'' mobilise toutes les ressources et toute l’attention de l’auteur, mais à elle est ordonnée toute une téléologie de l’itinéraire cornélien.
|Jacques Derrida
|Force and Signification, in ''Writing and Difference''
}}


===Rediscovering intra-medium movement===
===Rediscovering intra-medium movement===
Line 99: Line 111:
====Rediscovering intra-visuality. Restoring the primacy of the viewing angle.====
====Rediscovering intra-visuality. Restoring the primacy of the viewing angle.====


Keeping the interpretation intra-medium is counter-intuitive to most of us who have been accustomed to the signifier/signified dualism. “This painting represents the king”: this is a very natural statement to read, though it is hardly concerned with the objective content. If the reader of the statement sticks to what the interpretation '''actually communicates''', and tries to visualize a painting entirely through it, they would imagine a king sitting on a throne or a horse, a crown, or maybe a heraldic symbol. The visuals, along with all the non-visual facts (including the fact that this represents the king), contribute a “story” that goes beyond the mere visuals.
Keeping the interpretation intra-medium is counter-intuitive to most of us. “This painting represents the king”: this is a very natural statement to read, though it is hardly concerned with the objective content. If the reader of the statement sticks to what the interpretation '''actually communicates''', and tries to visualize a painting entirely through it, they would imagine a king sitting on a throne, a crown, maybe a heraldic symbol. The visuals, along with all the non-visual facts (including the fact that the king is represented), contribute a “story” that goes beyond the mere visuals.


{{quote|The ''Equestrian Portrait of Charles I'' (also known as ''Charles I on Horseback'') is an oil painting on canvas by Anthony van Dyck, showing Charles I on horseback. Charles I had become King of Great Britain and Ireland in 1625 on the death of his father James I, and Van Dyck became the Charles’ Principal Painter in Ordinary in 1632. This portrait is thought to have been painted in about 1637–38, only a few years before the English Civil War broke out in 1642. It is one of many portraits of Charles by Van Dyck, including several equestrian portraits.||English Wikipedia
{{quote|The ''Equestrian Portrait of Charles I'' (also known as ''Charles I on Horseback'') is an oil painting on canvas by Anthony van Dyck, showing Charles I on horseback. Charles I had become King of Great Britain and Ireland in 1625 on the death of his father James I, and Van Dyck became the Charles’ Principal Painter in Ordinary in 1632. This portrait is thought to have been painted in about 1637–38, only a few years before the English Civil War broke out in 1642. It is one of many portraits of Charles by Van Dyck, including several equestrian portraits.||English Wikipedia
Line 107: Line 119:
Such stories are independent of the visuals but it is assumed that these stories “merge” with the visuals and serve their meaning and, ultimately, value. They build a viewerless world:
Such stories are independent of the visuals but it is assumed that these stories “merge” with the visuals and serve their meaning and, ultimately, value. They build a viewerless world:


{{quote|But when we say that the for-itself is-in-the-world, that consciousness is consciousness of the world, '''we must be careful to remember that the world exists confronting consciousness as an indefinite multiplicity of reciprocal relations which consciousness surveys without perspective and contemplates without a point of view'''. ''For me'' this glass is to the left of the decanter and a little behind it; ''for Pierre'', it is to the right and a little in front. It is not even conceivable that a consciousness could survey the world in such a way that the glass should be simultaneously given to it at the right and at the left of the decanter, in front of it and behind it. This is by no means the consequence of a strict application of the principle of identity but because this fusion of right and left, of before and behind, would result in the total disappearance of “thises” at the heart of a primitive indistinction. Similarly if the table leg hides the designs in the rug from my sight, this is not the result of some finitude and some imperfection in my visual organs, but it is because a rug which would not be hidden by the table, a rug which would not be either under it or above it or to one side of it, would not have any relation of any kind with the table and would no longer belong to the “world” in which there is the table. The in-itself which is made manifest in the form of the ''this'' would return to its indifferent self-identity. Even space as a purely external relation would disappear. The constitution of space as a multiplicity of reciprocal relations can be effected only from the abstract point of view of science; it can not be lived, it can not even be represented. The triangle which I trace on the blackboard so as to help me in abstract reasoning is necessarily to the right of the circle tangent to one of its sides, necessarily to the extent that it is on the blackboard. And my effort is to surpass the concrete characteristics of the figure traced in chalk by not including its relation to me in my calculations any more than the thickness of the lines or the imperfection of the drawing.||Jean-Paul Sartre
{{quote|But when we say that the for-itself is-in-the-world, that consciousness is consciousness of the world, '''we must be careful to remember that the world exists confronting consciousness as an indefinite multiplicity of reciprocal relations which consciousness surveys without perspective and contemplates without a point of view'''. ''For me'' this glass is to the left of the decanter and a little behind it; ''for Pierre'', it is to the right and a little in front. It is not even conceivable that a consciousness could survey the world in such a way that the glass should be simultaneously given to it at the right and at the left of the decanter, in front of it and behind it. This is by no means the consequence of a strict application of the principle of identity but because this fusion of right and left, of before and behind, would result in the total disappearance of “thises” at the heart of a primitive indistinction. Similarly if the table leg hides the designs in the rug from my sight, this is not the result of some finitude and some imperfection in my visual organs, but it is because a rug which would not be hidden by the table, a rug which would not be either under it or above it or to one side of it, would not have any relation of any kind with the table and would no longer belong to the “world” in which there is the table. The in-itself which is made manifest in the form of the ''this'' would return to its indifferent self-identity. Even space as a purely external relation would disappear. '''The constitution of space as a multiplicity of reciprocal relations can be effected only from the abstract point of view of science; it can not be lived, it can not even be represented'''. The triangle which I trace on the blackboard so as to help me in abstract reasoning is necessarily to the right of the circle tangent to one of its sides, necessarily to the extent that it is on the blackboard. And my effort is to surpass the concrete characteristics of the figure traced in chalk by not including its relation to me in my calculations any more than the thickness of the lines or the imperfection of the drawing.||Jean-Paul Sartre
|''Being and Nothingness'', The Body as Being-For-Itself: Facticity, 2
|''Being and Nothingness'', The Body as Being-For-Itself: Facticity, 2
}}
}}


In the viewerless world '''signified''' by the painting, the king is not a bi-dimensional figure on a surface. The work could very well be a sculpture without invalidating a single word of the interpretation, down to the smallest detail:
In the viewerless world '''signified''' by the painting, the king is not just a bi-dimensional figure on a surface. The work could very well be a sculpture without invalidating a single word of the interpretation, down to the smallest detail:


{{quote|Charles is depicted wearing the same suit of armour, riding a heavily muscled dun horse with peculiarly small head. To the right, a page proffers a helmet. Charles appears as a heroic philosopher king, contemplatively surveying his domain, carrying a baton of command, with a long sword to his side, and wearing the medallion of the Sovereign of the Order of the Garter. His melancholy, distant expression was seen as a sign of wisdom. He wears the same suit of tilt armour in both equestrian paintings […]
{{quote|Charles is depicted wearing the same suit of armour, riding a heavily muscled dun horse with peculiarly small head. To the right, a page proffers a helmet. Charles appears as a heroic philosopher king, contemplatively surveying his domain, carrying a baton of command, with a long sword to his side, and wearing the medallion of the Sovereign of the Order of the Garter. His melancholy, distant expression was seen as a sign of wisdom. He wears the same suit of tilt armour in both equestrian paintings […]
Line 127: Line 139:
=====How the perception of uniqueness is biased because of clichés=====
=====How the perception of uniqueness is biased because of clichés=====


There is nothing trivial or objective in the assumption that all paintings must be interpreted as representing things. Picasso’s ''Mandolin Player'' might not be the obfuscated representation of a mandolin player. Even if it was, I would argue that the observer gains nothing from knowing it. What makes this assembly of geometrical patterns stand out as such, and not just be the equal of the sculpture of a mandolin player, or even the photograph of a mandolin player?
There is nothing trivial or objective in the assumption that all paintings must be interpreted as representing things. Picasso’s ''Mandolin Player'' might not be the obfuscated representation of a mandolin player. Even if it was, I would argue that it’s not the interesting part. What makes this assembly of geometrical patterns stand out as such, and not just be the equal of the sculpture of a mandolin player, or even the photograph of a mandolin player?


Sure, the overwhelming majority of painters actually wish for people to perceive their work as representations. But the point is not necessarily about the artist’s intention, but the potential of interpretation in general, and how people routinely put a ceiling on it—e.g., in abstract art, when the reviewer attempts, sometimes desperately, to figure out what may lurk behind the abstract:
Sure, the overwhelming majority of painters actually wish for people to perceive their work as representations. But the point is not necessarily about the artist’s intention, but the potential of interpretation in general, and how people routinely put a ceiling on it—e.g., in abstract art, when the reviewer attempts, sometimes desperately, to figure out what may lurk behind the abstract:
Line 143: Line 155:
In a preconception-free interpretation of the visuals, there would be no place for such a thing as confusion and “not making sense.” Only bringing up one’s preconceptions does that. “It is hard to tell where one musician starts and another stops, '''because''' the shapes that create them intersect and overlap”: it '''is''' confusing in regard to the expectation of a certain kind of figures, but confusingly enough, the exact way shapes “intersect and overlap” doesn’t suffer any confusion. And the exact way they “intersect and overlap” may precisely be the whole point. If you look at the patches of blue, they induce a kind of dislocated figure: it has a chin borrowed from the white musician, eyes borrowed from the harlequin, and it has legs, too. This figure is a painting-specific recurrence of structure. It doesn’t encumber itself with likelihood.
In a preconception-free interpretation of the visuals, there would be no place for such a thing as confusion and “not making sense.” Only bringing up one’s preconceptions does that. “It is hard to tell where one musician starts and another stops, '''because''' the shapes that create them intersect and overlap”: it '''is''' confusing in regard to the expectation of a certain kind of figures, but confusingly enough, the exact way shapes “intersect and overlap” doesn’t suffer any confusion. And the exact way they “intersect and overlap” may precisely be the whole point. If you look at the patches of blue, they induce a kind of dislocated figure: it has a chin borrowed from the white musician, eyes borrowed from the harlequin, and it has legs, too. This figure is a painting-specific recurrence of structure. It doesn’t encumber itself with likelihood.


The classical concept of figure belongs, with other concepts such as history, location, and meaning, to an implicit culture. This culture is oblivious to painting-specific narratives, favoring instead clichés. The clichés are anticipated, to the point that non-clichés are '''only recognized where we are looking for the clichés'''. In Hans Holbein’s ''The Ambassadors'', Slavoj Žižek calls the bizarre anamorphic skull in the center “the blot”: an inaccessible, obscure object of desire.
The classical concept of figure belongs, with other concepts such as history, location, and meaning, to an implicit culture. This culture is oblivious to painting-specific narratives, favoring instead clichés. The clichés are anticipated, to the point that non-clichés are '''only recognized because we are looking for the clichés'''. In Hans Holbein’s ''The Ambassadors'', Slavoj Žižek calls the bizarre anamorphic skull in the center “the blot”: an inaccessible, obscure object of desire.


[[Image:600px-Hans Holbein the Younger - The Ambassadors - Google Art Project.jpg|thumb|center|500px|Hans Holbein’s ''The Ambassadors'']]
[[Image:600px-Hans Holbein the Younger - The Ambassadors - Google Art Project.jpg|thumb|center|500px|Hans Holbein’s ''The Ambassadors'']]


The blot is most unusual, but isn’t it also unusual that in Cézanne’s ''The Nude Bather'', an expanse of mountain in the background runs parallel to the flat ground and slopes off at a certain angle?
The blot is most unusual, but isn’t it also unusual that in Cézanne’s ''The Nude Bather'', an expanse of mountain in the background runs parallel to the flat ground and slopes off in a way that mirrors the shape of the puddle at the bather’s feet?


[[Image:The-bather.jpg|thumb|center|400px|Isn’t the shape and position of the mountain in the background most unusual in relation to the other elements in Cézanne’s ''The Nude Bather'' ?]]
[[Image:The-bather.jpg|thumb|center|400px|Isn’t the shape and position of the mountain in the background most unusual in relation to the other elements in Cézanne’s ''The Nude Bather'' ?]]


The blot in ''The Ambassadors'' is instantly recognized as such through the contrast with a certain preconception of painting. But in the painting-specific narrative, the fact that it doesn’t play more of a role than any similarly shaped figure would—say, a quill slanting at the same angle—reveals the interpretive bias in both the cliché and the non-cliché. As a manner of speaking, there are “blots” everywhere. Cézanne sought them in vases, fruits, and silver cutlery. Anyone can find blots looking at the racks of vegetables in a supermarket.
The blot in ''The Ambassadors'' is instantly recognized as such by confronting certain expectations. But in the painting-specific narrative, the fact that it doesn’t play more of a role than any similarly shaped figure would—say, a quill slanting at the same angle—reveals the interpretive bias in both the cliché and the non-cliché. As a manner of speaking, there are “blots” everywhere. Cézanne sought them in vases, fruits, and silver cutlery. Anyone can find blots looking at the racks of vegetables in a supermarket.


Flatness in Modernist painting was, in the beginning, a non-cliché that fed off the clichés. For Clement Greenberg, the “purity” of “[https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Medium_specificity medium specificity]” is the affirmation of its independence from the figurative:
Flatness in Modernist painting was, in the beginning, a non-cliché that fed off the clichés. For Clement Greenberg, the “purity” of “[https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Medium_specificity medium specificity]” is the affirmation of its independence from the figurative:
Line 157: Line 169:
{{quote|The essence of Modernism lies, as I see it, in the use of characteristic methods of a discipline to criticize the discipline itself, not in order to subvert it but in order to entrench it more firmly in its area of competence. […]
{{quote|The essence of Modernism lies, as I see it, in the use of characteristic methods of a discipline to criticize the discipline itself, not in order to subvert it but in order to entrench it more firmly in its area of competence. […]


It quickly emerged that the unique and proper area of competence of each art coincided with all that was unique in the nature of its medium. The task of self-criticism became to eliminate from the specific effects of each art any and every effect that might conceivably be borrowed from or by the medium of any other art. Thus would each art be rendered “pure,” and in its “purity” find the guarantee of its standards of quality as well as of its independence. “Purity” meant self-definition, and the enterprise of self-criticism in the arts became one of self-definition with a vengeance.
It quickly emerged that the unique and proper area of competence of each art coincided with all that was unique in the nature of its medium. '''The task of self-criticism became to eliminate from the specific effects of each art any and every effect that might conceivably be borrowed from or by the medium of any other art. Thus would each art be rendered “pure,” and in its “purity” find the guarantee of its standards of quality as well as of its independence'''. “Purity” meant self-definition, and the enterprise of self-criticism in the arts became one of self-definition with a vengeance.


Realistic, naturalistic art had dissembled the medium, using art to conceal art; Modernism used art to call attention to art. The limitations that constitute the medium of painting—the flat surface, the shape of the support, the properties of the pigment—were treated by the Old Masters as negative factors that could be acknowledged only implicitly or indirectly. Under Modernism these same limitations came to be regarded as positive factors, and were acknowledged openly. Manet’s became the first Modernist pictures by virtue of the frankness with which they declared the flat surfaces on which they were painted. The Impressionists, in Manet’s wake, abjured underpainting and glazes, to leave the eye under no doubt as to the fact that the colors they used were made of paint that came from tubes or pots. Cézanne sacrificed verisimilitude, or correctness, in order to fit his drawing and design more explicitly to the rectangular shape of the canvas.||Clement Greenberg
Realistic, naturalistic art had dissembled the medium, using art to conceal art; Modernism used art to call attention to art. The limitations that constitute the medium of painting—the flat surface, the shape of the support, the properties of the pigment—were treated by the Old Masters as negative factors that could be acknowledged only implicitly or indirectly. Under Modernism these same limitations came to be regarded as positive factors, and were acknowledged openly. Manet’s became the first Modernist pictures by virtue of the frankness with which they declared the flat surfaces on which they were painted. The Impressionists, in Manet’s wake, abjured underpainting and glazes, to leave the eye under no doubt as to the fact that the colors they used were made of paint that came from tubes or pots. Cézanne sacrificed verisimilitude, or correctness, in order to fit his drawing and design more explicitly to the rectangular shape of the canvas.||Clement Greenberg
Line 187: Line 199:
}}
}}


This “usefulness” of “pure” art helped propel the “best” art over the lesser art, but there’s a caveat. The claim that the best art comes about by emphasizing “the flat surface, the shape of the support, the properties of the pigment” doesn’t actually communicate any demarcation between “best” and lesser art; Greenberg certainly came across pure paintings he found more pointless than others, unless he is to pure paintings what Marilyn Burns of ''Texas Chainsaw Massacre'' fame is to horror movies, according to this interview:
This “usefulness” of “pure” art helped propel the “best” art over the lesser art, but there’s a caveat. The claim that the best art comes about by emphasizing “the flat surface, the shape of the support, the properties of the pigment” doesn’t actually communicate any demarcation between “best” and lesser art; Greenberg certainly came across pure paintings he found more pointless than others, unless he is to pure paintings what Marilyn Burns of ''Texas Chainsaw Massacre'' fame is to movies, according to this interview:


{{quote|TT: Do you have a favorite?
{{quote|TT: Do you have a favorite?
Line 205: Line 217:
}}
}}


Purity isn’t enough of a criterion to demarcate art—at least it hasn’t been for a while, because it’s become a trope. But it contrasts nicely with a cultural bias for figurative painting as a cliché. As soon as both pure and non-pure paintings became equally accepted by the public, purity revealed itself to be too coarse as a criterion. In fact, non-pure paintings, even photographs, can be interpreted in terms of “the flat surface, the shape of the support, the properties of the pigment.” I could also “purify” any painting by overlaying it with solid colors, and I certainly wouldn’t expect Greenberg to hang it up there with his so-called “best art.” Reciprocally, non-pure art, such as photographs, can be interpreted through a purity lens. This photograph from Jay Maisel, ''Damsels wearing face packs posing before panels'', illustrates this:
Purity isn’t enough of a criterion to demarcate great art—at least it hasn’t been for a while, because it’s become a trope. As soon as both pure and non-pure paintings became equally accepted by the public, purity revealed itself to be too coarse as a criterion. In fact, non-pure paintings, even photographs, can be interpreted in terms of “the flat surface, the shape of the support, the properties of the pigment.” I could also “purify” any painting by overlaying it with solid colors, and I certainly wouldn’t expect Greenberg to hang it up there with his so-called “best art.” Likewise, non-pure art, such as photographs, can be interpreted through a purity lens. This photograph from Jay Maisel, ''Damsels wearing face packs posing before panels'', illustrates this:


[[Image:Jay maisel face packs.jpg|thumb|center|400px|Jay Maisel, ''Damsels wearing face packs posing before panels'']]
[[Image:Jay maisel face packs.jpg|thumb|center|400px|Jay Maisel, ''Damsels wearing face packs posing before panels'']]


The composition divides the surface into convex regions encompassing one woman each. The separation is further accentuated by the panels in the background. It’s particularly formal.
The composition divides the surface into convex regions encompassing each woman. The separation is further accentuated by the panels in the background. It’s particularly formal:


[[Image:Jay maisel face packs marked.png|thumb|center|400px|]]
[[Image:Jay maisel face packs marked.png|thumb|center|400px|]]


To be more accurate, the panels lead to the right, accompanying the left forearm/elbow of the woman to the right, and pointing “outside” the painting. The left hand of the woman follows the convex shape (dashed line around her head):
To be more accurate, the panels accompany the left forearm/elbow of the woman to the right. The left hand of the woman follows the convex shape (dashed red line around her head):


[[Image:Jay maisel face packs marked2.png|thumb|center|400px|]]
[[Image:Jay maisel face packs marked2.png|thumb|center|400px|]]


but the left elbow “moves” it in the direction sketched by the contour of the lockers. It is a kind of “mutant” motif derived from the motif created by the face mask (cf. yellow highlights). Note how the latter differs from the face mask of the other woman.
but the left forearm/elbow “moves” it in the direction sketched by the contour of the lockers. It is a kind of “mutant” motif derived from the motif created by the face mask (cf. blue highlights). Note how the latter differs from the closed-off face mask of the other woman.


The photograph is obviously figurative. But its formality also denotes a medium-specific narrative. It isn’t a mere matter of opposition between purity and non-purity. The described medium-specific narrative very specifically relies on connections between elements of human figures: the left hand connecting to the left forearm, the left hand connecting to the shape of the facemask through the color of the skin, and so on.
The photograph is obviously figurative. But its formality also ostentates a medium-specific narrative. It isn’t a mere matter of opposition between purity and non-purity. The described medium-specific narrative very specifically relies on connections between elements of human figures: the left hand connecting to the left forearm, the left hand connecting to the shape of the facemask through the color of the skin, and so on.


The interpretation of medium-specific narratives stresses uniqueness and doesn’t see (non)flatness. This remotely echoes the sentiment of certain authors like Deleuze and Guattari, who not only criticize the “order of the signifying and the figure,” but also its opposite, the “pure figural” as a “transgression… that remain[s] secondary nonetheless,” that is, secondary to the “schizophreny as process”:
The interpretation of medium-specific narratives stresses visual patterns and doesn’t see (non)flatness. This remotely echoes the sentiment of certain authors like Deleuze and Guattari, who not only criticize the “order of the signifying and the figure,” but also its opposite, the “pure figural” as a “transgression… that remain[s] secondary nonetheless,” that is, secondary to the “schizophreny as process”:


{{quote|[…] Lyotard shows in very beautiful pages that what is ''operating'' inside the dream is not the signifying, but a figural underneath, producing image configurations that use words, make them flow and traverse them following flows and positions that are not linguistic, without depending on neither the signifying nor its regulated elements. Everywhere, Lyotard destroys the order of the signifying and the figure. Rather than having the figures depend on the signifying and its effects, the signifying chain depends on the figural effects, the chain itself made up of asignifying signs, overwriting the signifying as well as the signified, treating the words like things, fabricating new units, producing, with the help of non-figurative figures, image configurations that ebb and flow […] The element of the pure figural, the “matrix-figure,” Lyotard actually calls it desire, that which leads us to the gates of schizophreny as process. But where does the reader’s impression come from, that Lyotard never ceases to stop the process, to recall the schizes to the shores that he just left, coded or overcoded territories, spaces and structures, '''where they only bring “transgressions,” disorders and distortions that remain secondary nonetheless''', rather than form and carry away the desiring machines that oppose the structures, the intensities that oppose space? Despite his attempt at binding desire to a fundamental yes, Lyotard reintroduces lack and absence in desire, keeps it under the law of castration at the risk of bringing back the whole signifying with it, and discovers the matrix-figure in the fantasm, the mere fantasm that obscures the desiring production, all desire as effective production.|[…] dans le rêve, Lyotard montre dans de très belles pages que ce qui ''travaille'' n’est pas le signifiant, mais un figural en dessous, faisant surgir des configurations d’images qui se servent des mots, les font couler et les coupent suivant des flux et des points qui ne sont pas linguistiques, en ne dépendent pas du signifiant ni de ses éléments réglés. Partout donc Lyotard renverse l’ordre du signifiant et de la figure. Ce ne sont pas les figures qui dépendent du signifiant et de ses effets, c’est la chaîne signifiante qui dépend des effets figuraux, faite elle-même de signes asignifiants, écrasant les signifiants comme les signifiés, traîtant les mots comme des choses, fabriquant de nouvelles unités, faisant avec des figures non figuratives des configurations d’images qui se font et se défont. […] L’élément du figural pur, la “figure-matrice,” Lyotard la nomme bien désir, qui nous conduit aux portes de la schizophrénie comme processus. Mais d’où vient pourtant l’impression du lecteur que Lyotard n’a de cesse d’arrêter le processus, et de rabattre les schizes sur les rivages qu’il vient de quitter, territoires codés ou surcodés, espaces et structures, ''''où ils ne font plus qu’apporter des “trangressions,” des troubles et des déformations malgré tout secondaires''', au lieu de former et d’emporter plus loin les machines désirantes qui s’opposent aux structures, les intensités qui s’opposent aux espaces ? C’est que, malgré sa tentative de lier le désir à un oui fondamental, Lyotard réintroduit le manque et l’absence dans le désir, le maintient sous la loi de castration au risque de ramener avec elle tout le signifiant, et découvre la matrice de la figure dans le fantasme, le simple fantasme qui vient occulter la production désirante, tout le désir comme production effective.|Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari
{{quote|[…] Lyotard shows in very beautiful pages that what is ''operating'' inside the dream is not the signifying, but a figural underneath, producing image configurations that use words, make them flow and traverse them following flows and positions that are not linguistic, without depending on neither the signifying nor its regulated elements. Everywhere, Lyotard destroys the order of the signifying and the figure. Rather than having the figures depend on the signifying and its effects, the signifying chain depends on the figural effects, the chain itself made up of asignifying signs, overwriting the signifying as well as the signified, treating the words like things, fabricating new units, producing, with the help of non-figurative figures, image configurations that ebb and flow […] The element of the pure figural, the “matrix-figure,” Lyotard actually calls it desire, that which leads us to the gates of schizophreny as process. But where does the reader’s impression come from, that Lyotard never ceases to stop the process, to recall the schizes to the shores that he just left, coded or overcoded territories, spaces and structures, '''where they only bring “transgressions,” disorders and distortions that remain secondary nonetheless''', rather than form and carry away the desiring machines that oppose the structures, the intensities that oppose space? Despite his attempt at binding desire to a fundamental yes, Lyotard reintroduces lack and absence in desire, keeps it under the law of castration at the risk of bringing back the whole signifying with it, and discovers the matrix-figure in the fantasm, the mere fantasm that obscures the desiring production, all desire as effective production.|[…] dans le rêve, Lyotard montre dans de très belles pages que ce qui ''travaille'' n’est pas le signifiant, mais un figural en dessous, faisant surgir des configurations d’images qui se servent des mots, les font couler et les coupent suivant des flux et des points qui ne sont pas linguistiques, en ne dépendent pas du signifiant ni de ses éléments réglés. Partout donc Lyotard renverse l’ordre du signifiant et de la figure. Ce ne sont pas les figures qui dépendent du signifiant et de ses effets, c’est la chaîne signifiante qui dépend des effets figuraux, faite elle-même de signes asignifiants, écrasant les signifiants comme les signifiés, traîtant les mots comme des choses, fabriquant de nouvelles unités, faisant avec des figures non figuratives des configurations d’images qui se font et se défont. […] L’élément du figural pur, la “figure-matrice,” Lyotard la nomme bien désir, qui nous conduit aux portes de la schizophrénie comme processus. Mais d’où vient pourtant l’impression du lecteur que Lyotard n’a de cesse d’arrêter le processus, et de rabattre les schizes sur les rivages qu’il vient de quitter, territoires codés ou surcodés, espaces et structures, ''''où ils ne font plus qu’apporter des “trangressions,” des troubles et des déformations malgré tout secondaires''', au lieu de former et d’emporter plus loin les machines désirantes qui s’opposent aux structures, les intensités qui s’opposent aux espaces ? C’est que, malgré sa tentative de lier le désir à un oui fondamental, Lyotard réintroduit le manque et l’absence dans le désir, le maintient sous la loi de castration au risque de ramener avec elle tout le signifiant, et découvre la matrice de la figure dans le fantasme, le simple fantasme qui vient occulter la production désirante, tout le désir comme production effective.|Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari
|Savages, barbarians and civilized men, in ''Anti-Œdipus''}}
|Savages, barbarians and civilized men, in ''Anti-Œdipus''}}


The interpretation of the medium-specific narrative doesn’t rely on a general theory of art, nor on a theory of the medium such as “medium purity.” It doesn’t rely on a theory of the “very best art of the last hundred-odd years,” either. Any consensus on “the best art” is based on clichés, and content-bound interpretation doesn’t know any clichés (which, by the way, means it also doesn’t know parody and shock value).
The interpretation of the medium-specific narrative doesn’t rely on a general theory of art, nor on a theory of the medium such as “medium purity.” It doesn’t rely on a theory of the “very best art of the last hundred-odd years,” either. Any consensus on “the best art” is based on clichés, and the interpretation of the medium-specific narrative doesn’t look for clichés.


=====Rediscovering graphical narration. Real-time sand art as an eye-opener. Why graphical narration in movies is so rare. The example of The Vanishing. A comics-specific narrative from Goossens’ ''Touti and his exhaust pipe''.=====
=====Rediscovering graphical narration. Real-time sand art as an eye-opener. Graphical narration in movies. A comics-specific narrative from Goossens’ ''Touti and his exhaust pipe''.=====


When it comes to single images, it seems weird to speak of a narrative, much less an epic one. But this weirdness is a result of an amnesic way of looking at images. For if one would only be so inclined as to take the placement of a house, the branch of a tree, or the directionality of the texture of a loaf of bread, to be as relevant to the image as death is to a crime novel, one would immediately see the potential of a “graphical story” with multiple heretofore ignored “graphical events.” The events are the visual sensations as our gaze moves across the canvas. Each transition, each intersection, each similarity can be recorded into a medium-specific narrative, just like storyline events are recorded into the timeline of a regular novel.
When it comes to single images, it seems weird to speak of a narrative. But this weirdness is a result of an amnesic way of looking at images. For if one would only be so inclined as to take the placement of a house, the branch of a tree, or the directionality of the texture of a loaf of bread, to be as relevant to the image as death is to a crime novel, one would immediately see the potential of a “graphical story” with multiple heretofore ignored “graphical events.” The events are the visual sensations as our gaze moves across the canvas. Each color transition, each intersection, each pattern can be recorded into a medium-specific narrative, just like storyline events are recorded into the timeline of a regular novel.


These graphical events can be insisted upon through cinematic means: narration across image sequences (polyptichs, comic strips), or animations. In this performace on ''Britain’s Got Talent: The Champions'', Kseniya Simonova uses real-time sand art to tell a 3-minute graphical story. Here, a bird flock progressively morphs into the facial features of a school girl:
These graphical events can be insisted upon through cinematic means: image sequences (polyptichs, comic strips) or animations. In this performace on ''Britain’s Got Talent: The Champions'', Kseniya Simonova uses real-time sand art to tell a 3-minute graphical story. Here, a bird flock progressively morphs into the facial features of a school girl:


[[Image:Sandart0.jpg|center|300px]]
[[Image:Sandart0.jpg|center|300px]]
Line 240: Line 252:
[[Image:Sandart1.jpg|center|300px]]
[[Image:Sandart1.jpg|center|300px]]


The sky darkens and lightning strikes. Then the lightning becomes IV lines as the girl gets transposed into a hospital room:
The sky darkens. Lightning strikes, then it becomes IV lines as the girl gets transposed into a hospital room:


[[Image:Sandart2.jpg|center|300px]]
[[Image:Sandart2.jpg|center|300px]]
Line 248: Line 260:
[[Image:Sandart3.jpg|center|300px]]
[[Image:Sandart3.jpg|center|300px]]


This kind of graphical narration that is almost unheard of in cinematography, even though cinematography can technically do everything sand art does. In the The very fact that conveyed story (in the traditional sense) is so cheesy and almost empty (a child gets hospitalized and recovers), makes the graphical story stand out all the more.  
This kind of graphics-specific narration is a rarity in movies, even though movies can technically do everything sand art does. Their main focus is on traditional narratives, which is reflected by the fact that many movies are adaptations of written stories. On the other hand, sand art is rather light on story. In our example, the story is actually so cheesy (a child gets hospitalized then recovers, and it all ends with the line “Never give up”) that it would make an embarassing movie without the graphics-specific narrative. It should be noted that the medium specificity emphasized here is graphical and ignores the technicality of performing with sand. By comparison, another cinematic form, shadow play dancing (e.g., the band [https://agt.fandom.com/wiki/Silhouettes Silhouettes] which performed on America’s Got Talent), tends to depict stories that are as cheesy but without the graphics-specific narration, as its focus is more on the technicality of creating mundane shapes with human shadows.
 
Movies with distinctive medium-specific narratives do exist though, such as ''The Vanishing'' (1988), itself a book adaptation. In that film, a car is inside a tunnel. Inside, a woman, called Saskia, tells her man, Rex Hoffman:
 
“My nightmare. I had it again last night.”
 
Hoffman remembers:
 
“That you’re inside a '''golden egg''', and you can’t get out, and you float all alone through space forever.”
 
The car runs out of gas inside the tunnel. After a brief argument, Hoffman leaves a panicking Saskia in the car to seek help. When he comes back with a can, she’s not in the car anymore. He drives the car out of the tunnel, and as he emerges, he sees her framed by the bright opening of the tunnel, almost like a golden egg:
 
[[Image:Thevanishing1.jpg|center|300px]]
 
At the next rest area, Saskia disappears, probably abducted. Years later, Hoffman still obsesses over her disappearance and does everything in his power to learn what happened to her. On television, he recounts:
 
“She dreamed that we’d meet somewhere in space, each of us imprisoned inside a golden egg. In my dream, we also found each other, out there in space. And I’ve interpreted this dream as a sign.”
 
When he finally meets the abductor, he says:
 
“I don’t want to punish you. I don’t care about you. '''All I want to know is what happened to her'''.


In , , because the focus is on the traditional story. That’s why so many movies work as adaptations of written stories to the screen. There are exceptions though. For example, ''The Vanishing'' (1993), itself a book adaptation,
The abductor agrees to let him know but only under the condition that he lets himself get put into sleep. He accepts after an intense inner debate. He wakes up in the dark and bangs his head while trying to get up. Using a lighter he finds out that he’s stuck inside a coffin. The lighter’s flame fades into the memory of the tunnel opening with Saskia inside:


Actually, the 2000 Hollywood remake () takes away all the graphical narration in favor of action movie tropes.
[[Image:Thevanishing2.jpg|center|300px]]


Daniel Goossens’ comic ''Touti and his exhaust pipe'' nicely illustrates the difference between graphical and event-based story-telling. Comics feature two pedagogical advantages over traditional painting: their obviously narrative format, and text. Captions can narrate events just like event-based story-telling, but they can also introduce a self-aware “break-the-fourth-wall” voice that can force the reader to rethink their relationship to the visual medium, often with a comical effect not unlike René Magritte’s ''This is not a pipe''.
The last shot of the movie is of a newspaper showing the portraits of Saskia and Hoffman side by side.
 
[[Image:Thevanishing3.jpg|center|300px]]
 
Then, a black mask is superimposed over the newspaper, enclosing the portraits inside egg shapes:
 
[[Image:Thevanishing4.jpg|center|300px]]
 
A medium-specific narrative therefore leads to fulfilling the golden egg prophecy in a very visual interpretation, from the lighting of the inside of the coffin to the newspaper portraits. Interestingly, the 1993 Hollywood remake, by the same director, takes away the medium-specific narration in favor of action movie tropes.
 
Daniel Goossens’ comic ''Touti and his exhaust pipe'' nicely illustrates the difference between graphical and event-based story-telling. Comics feature two pedagogical advantages over traditional painting: their narrative format, and text. Captions can narrate events, so they can force a break-the-fourth-wall point-of-view onto the reader, leading them to rethink their relationship to the visual medium, often with a comical effect not unlike René Magritte’s ''This is not a pipe''.


[[Image:MagrittePipe.jpg|thumb|center|300px|René Magritte’s ''This is not a pipe'']]
[[Image:MagrittePipe.jpg|thumb|center|300px|René Magritte’s ''This is not a pipe'']]
Line 262: Line 304:
[[Image:DSC00307.png|thumb|center|500px|Page 2 of Goossens’s ''Touti and his exhaust pipe'']]
[[Image:DSC00307.png|thumb|center|500px|Page 2 of Goossens’s ''Touti and his exhaust pipe'']]


The policeman seems to signal Touti to pull over because of the malfunctioning exhaust pipe, but he corrects the narrator: “No, it’s not for that. It’s to interrupt the monotony. Here, in the flat lands, the horizon [author’s note: cf. blue highlight] is monotonous, and it is fitting that a policeman cuts through it using his silhouette [author’s note: cf. red highlight].”  
The policeman seems to signal Touti to pull over because of a malfunctioning exhaust pipe, but he corrects the narrator: “No, it’s not for that. It’s to interrupt the monotony. Here, in the flat lands, the horizon [cf. blue highlight] is monotonous, and it is fitting that a policeman cuts through it using his silhouette [cf. red highlight].”  


His speech (comically) emphasizes his '''verticality''' rather than the concept of “officer of the Law.” The story then builds up toward a car crash:
His speech (comically) emphasizes his '''verticality''' rather than the concept of “officer of the Law.” The story then builds up toward a car crash:
Line 268: Line 310:
[[Image:DSC00309.png|thumb|center|500px|Page 3 of Goossens’s ''Touti and his exhaust pipe'']]
[[Image:DSC00309.png|thumb|center|500px|Page 3 of Goossens’s ''Touti and his exhaust pipe'']]


Remarkably enough, the car runs into a tree (red highlight) “cutting through the horizon (blue highlight)” just like the vertical officer. A “comics-specific” narrative thus emerges.
Remarkably enough, the car runs into a tree [red highlight] “cutting through the horizon [blue highlight]” just like the vertical officer. A comics-specific narrative thus emerges.


The interpretation of this story changes altogether when one switches to a traditional viewpoint. The policeman’s appearance becomes a casual event in the timeline. When all is said and done, all he did was advise Touti to have his exhaust pipe changed. By ending on a car crash, the story expresses the “irony of fate:” at the time of the crash, the car had just been repaired, and to add insult to injury, the tragic turn of events came about due to the advice of the policeman. This interpretation is independent from the graphical representation. For example, seeing the crash from above, instead of having the tree “cut through the horizon,” wouldn’t change anything. It would be a graphically different, but story-wise identical, collision, and a different medium-specific narrative (in particular, the reference to the officer would get obscured).
The story changes altogether when one switches to a more traditional interpretation. The policeman’s appearance becomes a casual event in the timeline. When all is said and done, all he did was advise Touti to have his exhaust pipe changed. By ending on a car crash, the story expresses the “irony of fate:” at the time of the crash, the car had just been repaired, and to add insult to injury, the tragic turn of events came about due to the advice of the policeman. This interpretation is independent from the graphical representation. For example, seeing the crash from above, instead of having the tree “cut through the horizon,” wouldn’t change the interpretation. There would be a graphically different, but story-wise identical, collision, and a different medium-specific narrative (without the graphical reference to the officer).


====Rediscovering intra-textuality====
====Rediscovering intra-textuality====
Line 276: Line 318:
=====Staying inside the text medium: the New Criticism movement. The cliché/non-cliché bias.=====
=====Staying inside the text medium: the New Criticism movement. The cliché/non-cliché bias.=====


Traditionally, interpretation treats prose differently from poetry, poetry differently from sound poetry, etc. We naturally expect interpretations of poems to be more medium-specific than interpretations of novels, if only because they will be more attentive to text-specific things like phrasal structure, rhyming, and so on. Yet, this couldn’t prevent schools of thought such as the New Criticism:
Traditionally, interpretation treats prose differently from poetry, poetry differently from sound poetry, etc. We naturally expect interpretations of poems to be more medium-specific than interpretations of novels, if only because they will be more attentive to text-specific things like phrasal structure, rhyming, and so on:


{{quote|New Criticism developed as a reaction to the older philological and literary history schools, which, influenced by nineteenth-century German scholarship, focused on the history and meaning of individual words and their relation to foreign and ancient languages, comparative sources, and the biographical circumstances of the authors. These approaches, it was felt, tended to distract from the text and meaning of a poem and entirely neglect its aesthetic qualities in favor of teaching about external factors. On the other hand, the literary appreciation school, which limited itself to pointing out the “beauties” and morally elevating qualities of the text, was disparaged by the New Critics as too subjective and emotional. Condemning this as a version of Romanticism, they aimed for newer, systematic and objective method.
{{quote|New Criticism developed as a reaction to the older philological and literary history schools, which, influenced by nineteenth-century German scholarship, focused on the history and meaning of individual words and their relation to foreign and ancient languages, comparative sources, and the biographical circumstances of the authors. These approaches, it was felt, tended to distract from the text and meaning of a poem and entirely neglect its aesthetic qualities in favor of teaching about external factors. On the other hand, the literary appreciation school, which limited itself to pointing out the “beauties” and morally elevating qualities of the text, was disparaged by the New Critics as too subjective and emotional. Condemning this as a version of Romanticism, they aimed for newer, systematic and objective method.
Line 292: Line 334:
}}
}}


But just as the blot reveals a cultural bias for the figurative, there’s also an interpretive bias as soon as one ignores sound in places we don’t expect it to matter. Such is the case for the final lines of ''Ode on a Grecian Urn'', whose rhyme structure—“Beauty is truth, truth beauty, that is all/Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know”—went largely unattended by the majority of academics who chose instead to debate about the meaning and who truly spoke to whom: poet to reader, urn to reader, poet to urn, poet to figures on the urn?
But there’s an interpretive bias as soon as one ignores sound in places we don’t expect it to matter. Such is the case for the final lines of ''Ode on a Grecian Urn'', whose rhyme structure—“Beauty is truth, truth beauty, that is all/Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know”—wasn’t really interpreted by the majority of academics (and at best confused them) who chose instead to debate about the meaning and who truly spoke to whom: poet to reader, urn to reader, poet to urn, poet to figures on the urn?


=====The question of scale: the medium-specific micro-narratives=====
=====The question of scale: the medium-specific micro-narratives=====


Medium-specific narratives in literature are nothing new. For example, reasoning fallacies offer various forms of medium-specific narratives. What they lack in reality, scientific reliability, and practical applicability, they gain by being amusing, entertaining, witty, comical, interesting, artful, and limitless. Syllogistic fallacies could very well be described as “patterns of resolved stresses,” as the New Criticism describes poetry. “Stress” accrues with each additional premise, and the conclusion resolves the “stress” mostly by “sounding good:”
Medium-specific narratives in literature are nothing new. For example, reasoning fallacies offer various forms of medium-specific narratives. What they lack in reality, scientific reliability, and practical applicability, they gain by being amusing, entertaining, witty, comical, interesting, artful, and limitless. Syllogistic fallacies could very well be described as “patterns of resolved stresses,” as the New Criticism describes poetry. “Stress” accrues with each additional premise, and the conclusion resolves the “stress” mostly by “sounding natural:”


# All inhabitants of other planets drink water.
# All inhabitants of other planets drink water.
Line 314: Line 356:
# Therefore, my grandfather is a student.
# Therefore, my grandfather is a student.


The fallacy relies on symmetry, both semantically and structurally. Should the premises be very distinct from each other, fewer would be fooled into believing the conclusion. The following rewrite would be far less convincing:
The fallacy relies on symmetry, both semantically and structurally. Should the premises be very distinct from each other, this wouldn’t even be considered a good fallacy. The following rewrite would be far less convincing:


# All political leaders, doctors, and students have been young.
# All political leaders, doctors, and students have been young.
Line 320: Line 362:
# So he is a student.
# So he is a student.


In comparison, a rational conclusion is obvious, down-to-earth, tautological, uncomical.
In comparison, a rational conclusion is tediously obvious, down-to-earth, tautological, uncomical.


# All political leaders, doctors, and students have been young.
# All political leaders, doctors, and students have been young.
Line 326: Line 368:
# He may have been a political leader, a doctor, and/or a student, but it is not necessary.
# He may have been a political leader, a doctor, and/or a student, but it is not necessary.


Fallacies are not exclusive to well-known syllogisms that fit into 3 sentences. They rountinely occur in prose, most unassumingly in scientific literature. The reader doesn’t always need a science degree in order to detect the fallaciousness, because the fallacy, as a medium-specific narrative, is expressed by the text itself, in a self-contained way.
Fallacies are not just syllogisms that fit into 3 sentences. They routinely occur informally, most unassumingly in scientific literature. The reader doesn’t always need a science degree in order to detect them, because a fallacy, as a medium-specific narrative, can be expressed in the text itself, in a self-contained way.


Not all of science is equally weak to fallacy. Compared to axiomatic science, empirical science as a collection of universal laws (e.g., “the action is always equal to the reaction”) is more “entertaining,” whether because of the leaps of faith that, as Hume pointed out, are required to elevate experimental observations to universal statements, or because of the wishful thinking underneath their justification, especially in the fields of applied logic and mathematics. For example, in ''The Logic of Scientific Discovery'', Popper refutes the argument that his concept of “degree of corroboration of probability hypotheses” is reducible to traditional probability:
Not all of science is equally vulnerable to fallacy. Compared to axiomatic science, empirical science as a collection of universal laws (e.g., “the action is always equal to the reaction”) is more “entertaining,” whether because of the leaps of faith that, as Hume pointed out, are required to elevate experimental observations to universal statements, or because of the wishful thinking underneath their justification, especially in the fields of applied science. For example, in ''The Logic of Scientific Discovery'', Popper refutes the argument that his concept of “degree of corroboration of probability hypotheses” is reducible to traditional probability:


{{quote|1=Consider the next throw with a homogeneous die. Let x be the statement ‘six will turn up’; let y be its negation, that is to say, let y = ~x; and let z be the information ‘an even number will turn up’. We have the following absolute probabilities:
{{quote|1=Consider the next throw with a homogeneous die. Let x be the statement ‘six will turn up’; let y be its negation, that is to say, let y = ~x; and let z be the information ‘an even number will turn up’. We have the following absolute probabilities:
Line 370: Line 412:
But Popper is misleading when he equates C(x, z) < C(y, z) to “y has the property P in a higher degree than x,” because by definition, this would mean we have “p(y, z) > p(y) to a higher degree than p(x, z) > p(x).” We are comparing 2 statements (“p(y, z) > p(y)” on one hand, and “p(x, z) > p(x)” on the other) each with a different right-hand side, namely p(x) and p(y). I can say that Alice is taller than Bob in a higher degree than Cedric is taller than David, but it’s not contradictory to say that Cedric is taller than Alice.  
But Popper is misleading when he equates C(x, z) < C(y, z) to “y has the property P in a higher degree than x,” because by definition, this would mean we have “p(y, z) > p(y) to a higher degree than p(x, z) > p(x).” We are comparing 2 statements (“p(y, z) > p(y)” on one hand, and “p(x, z) > p(x)” on the other) each with a different right-hand side, namely p(x) and p(y). I can say that Alice is taller than Bob in a higher degree than Cedric is taller than David, but it’s not contradictory to say that Cedric is taller than Alice.  


So a more accurate metaphor for P would be “warmer” rather than just “warm,” with an important emphasis on warmer '''than something'''. Obviously, if one makes x warmer and y cooler, y can still be warmer than x because it was very hot to start with, so having C(x, z) < C(y, z) (“y is warmer than something, to a higher degree than x is warmer than something”) doesn’t seem contradictory anymore.
So a more accurate metaphor for P would be “warmer” rather than just “warm,” with an important emphasis on warmer '''than something'''. Obviously, if x gets warmer (Co(x, z)) and y cooler (¬Co(y, z)), y can still be warmer than x because it was very hot to start with, so having C(x, z) < C(y, z) (“y is warmer than something, to a higher degree than x is warmer than something”) doesn’t seem contradictory anymore.


Such losses in metaphor share with syllogisms the same propensity for erasing structural relationships by means of “literary devices,” such as the shortcut from “warmer” to “warm.” They underly an infinite number of unique narratives that occur when translating back and forth between informal and formal language. Popper himself debunks Heisenberg’s use of informal language in what belongs to the long list of sensationalist interpretations of numbers and formulas that theoretical physics is especially fond of (e.g., the many-worlds interpretation, Schrödinger’s cat, and time dilation):
Such losses in metaphor share with syllogisms the same propensity for erasing structural relationships through “honest mistakes” such as the shortcut from “warmer” to “warm.” They underly an infinite number of unique narratives that occur when translating back and forth between informal and formal language. Popper himself debunks Heisenberg’s use of informal language in what belongs to the long list of sensationalist interpretations of numbers and formulas that theoretical physics is especially fond of (e.g., the many-worlds interpretation, Schrödinger’s cat, time dilation):


{{quote|1=[The problem following here has since become famous under the name ‘The problem of the (discontinuous) reduction of the wave packet’. Some leading physicists told me in 1934 that they agreed with my trivial solution, yet the problem still plays a most bewildering role in the discussion of the quantum theory, after more than twenty years.]
{{quote|1=[The problem following here has since become famous under the name ‘The problem of the (discontinuous) reduction of the wave packet’. Some leading physicists told me in 1934 that they agreed with my trivial solution, yet the problem still plays a most bewildering role in the discussion of the quantum theory, after more than twenty years.]


Imagine a semi-translucent mirror, ''i.e.'' a mirror which reflects part of the light, and lets part of it through. The formally singular probability that one given photon (or light quantum) passes through the mirror, \(_αP_k(β)\), may be taken to be equal to the probability that it will be reflected; we therefore have
Imagine a semi-translucent mirror, ''i.e.'' a mirror which reflects part of the light, and lets part of it through. The formally singular probability that one given photon (or light quantum) passes through the mirror, <math>(_αP_k(β))</math>, may be taken to be equal to the probability that it will be reflected; we therefore have


\(_αP_k(β) = _αP_k(\bar{β}) = {1 \over 2}\)
<math>(_αP_k(β) = _αP_k(\bar{β}) = {1 \over 2})</math>


This probability estimate, as we know, is defined by objective statistical probabilities; that is to say, it is equivalent to the hypothesis that one half of a given class α of light quanta will pass through the mirror whilst the other half will be reflected. Now let a photon k fall upon the mirror; and let it next be experimentally ascertained that this photon has been reflected: then the probabilities seem to change suddenly, as it were, and discontinuously. It is as though before the experiment they had both been equal to \({1 \over 2}\), while after the fact of the reflection became known, they had suddenly turned into 0 and to 1, respectively. It is plain that this example is really the same as that given in section 71. [That is to say, the probabilities ‘change’ only in so far as α is replaced by β. Thus \(_αP(β)\) remains unchanged \({1 \over 2}\); but \(_\bar{β}P(β)\), of course, equals 0, just as \(_βP(β)\) equals 1.] And it hardly helps to clarify the situation if this experiment is described, as by Heisenberg, in such terms as the following: ‘By the experiment [i.e. the measurement by which we find the reflected photon], a kind of physical action (a reduction of wave packets) is exerted from the place where the reflected half of the wave packet is found upon another place—as distant as we choose—where the other half of the packet just happens to be’; a description to which he adds: ‘this physical action is one which spreads with super-luminal velocity.’ This is unhelpful since our original probabilities, \(_αP_k(β)\) and \(_αP_k(\bar{β})\), remain equal to \({1 \over 2}\). All that has happened is the choice of a new reference class—β or \(\bar{β}\), instead of α—a choice strongly suggested to us by the result of the experiment, i.e. by the information \(k \in β\) or \(k \in \bar{β}\), respectively. '''Saying of the logical consequences of this choice (or, perhaps, of the logical consequences of this information) that they ‘spread with super-luminal velocity’ is about as helpful as saying that twice two turns with super-luminal velocity into four'''. A further remark of Heisenberg’s, to the effect that this kind of propagation of a physical action cannot be used to transmit signals, though true, hardly improves matters.
This probability estimate, as we know, is defined by objective statistical probabilities; that is to say, it is equivalent to the hypothesis that one half of a given class α of light quanta will pass through the mirror whilst the other half will be reflected. Now let a photon k fall upon the mirror; and let it next be experimentally ascertained that this photon has been reflected: then the probabilities seem to change suddenly, as it were, and discontinuously. It is as though before the experiment they had both been equal to <math>({1 \over 2})</math>, while after the fact of the reflection became known, they had suddenly turned into 0 and to 1, respectively. It is plain that this example is really the same as that given in section 71. [That is to say, the probabilities ‘change’ only in so far as α is replaced by β. Thus <math>(_αP(β))</math> remains unchanged <math>({1 \over 2})</math>; but <math>(_\bar{β}P(β))</math>, of course, equals 0, just as <math>(_βP(β))</math> equals 1.] And it hardly helps to clarify the situation if this experiment is described, as by Heisenberg, in such terms as the following: ‘By the experiment [i.e. the measurement by which we find the reflected photon], a kind of physical action (a reduction of wave packets) is exerted from the place where the reflected half of the wave packet is found upon another place—as distant as we choose—where the other half of the packet just happens to be’; a description to which he adds: ‘this physical action is one which spreads with super-luminal velocity.’ This is unhelpful since our original probabilities, <math>(_αP_k(β))</math> and <math>(_αP_k(\bar{β}))</math>, remain equal to <math>({1 \over 2})</math>. All that has happened is the choice of a new reference class—β or <math>(\bar{β})</math>, instead of α—a choice strongly suggested to us by the result of the experiment, i.e. by the information <math>(k \in β)</math> or <math>(k \in \bar{β})</math>, respectively. '''Saying of the logical consequences of this choice (or, perhaps, of the logical consequences of this information) that they ‘spread with super-luminal velocity’ is about as helpful as saying that twice two turns with super-luminal velocity into four'''. A further remark of Heisenberg’s, to the effect that this kind of propagation of a physical action cannot be used to transmit signals, though true, hardly improves matters.
|2=
|2=
|3=Karl Popper
|3=Karl Popper
|4=''The Logic of Scientific Discovery''}}
|4=''The Logic of Scientific Discovery''}}


Most fallacies share the liberal use of language, but their form and scale vary, from syllogisms to elaborate theses.
Many fallacies share the liberal use of language, but their form and scale can vary from syllogisms to very elaborate theses.


=====Non-fiction literature=====
=====Non-fiction literature=====
Line 391: Line 433:
======Prerequisite to rediscovery: stoicism in the face of contradictions, errors and dislikes. Being open-minded and not limited by taste.======
======Prerequisite to rediscovery: stoicism in the face of contradictions, errors and dislikes. Being open-minded and not limited by taste.======


One has absolute freedom to overlook the medium-specific narratives. So does the author of fallacies. They can freely overlook their “shortcomings”—I put that in quotes, because fallacies may be inconsequential, or even work out for the best. Most would agree that contradictions in a scientific theory should be cause enough to ditch it. Yet, a self-contradictory theory has no shame. It will outlive its intolerant readers. It weaves a tissue of contradictions, contradictions that break conventions, “don’t make sense,” or are so full of involuntary errors that even the author repudiated their own work. Just like science fiction, it doesn’t matter.
One has absolute freedom to overlook the medium-specific narratives. So does the author of fallacies. They can freely overlook their “shortcomings”—I put that in quotes, because fallacies may be inconsequential, or even work out for the best. Most would agree that contradictions in a scientific theory should be cause enough to ditch it. Yet, a self-contradictory theory has no shame. It will outlive its intolerant readers. It weaves a tissue of contradictions, contradictions that break conventions, “don’t make sense,” or are so full of involuntary errors that even the author repudiated it. Just like science fiction, it doesn’t care.


When we ditch a logic system because it is self-contradictory, we do so for the same reason we ditch any other self-contradictory logic system: a single contradiction puts the whole system in jeopardy, since any proposition and its contrary can be logically derived from it. Yet the text that describes a self-contradictory logic system only mentions a very small subset of the infinite set of possible texts, and it does so in its own way. The confusion in Popper, as quoted in the previous section, is not only between the comparative and absolute forms, i.e., between “warm” and “warmer,” between “confirmed” and “confirmed to a higher degree.” There is a very medium-specific narrative that makes the confusion very peculiar. Popper makes the formula “Co(x, z) & ¬Co(y, z) & p(x, z) < p(y, z)” appear all the more self-contradictory because he '''first''' defined p(x, z) > p(x) as the absolute form Co(x, z) (“z confirms x”), which made it easier to think it is incompatible with the relative form “z confirms x to a lesser degree than z confirms y”. This is a case where the fallacy in the mix of formal and natural discourse highly depends on the presentation: introduce an abbrevation Co(x, z) that makes it easy to define (“z confirms x”) in an informal and amnesic way (forgetting the precise form of the inequality p(x, z) > p(x)), then compare the informal definition with another informal definition: there you have a medium-specific narrative.
When we ditch a logic system because it is self-contradictory, we do so for the same reason we ditch any other self-contradictory logic system: a single contradiction puts the whole system in jeopardy, since any proposition and its contrary can be logically derived from it. So, for example, if you prove 1 = 2, you can also prove 3 = 800. Yet the text that describes a self-contradictory logic system only mentions a very small subset of the infinite set of possible texts, and it does so in its own way. The confusion in Popper, as quoted in the previous section, is not only between the comparative and absolute forms, i.e., between “warm” and “warmer,” between “confirmed” and “confirmed to a higher degree.” There is a very medium-specific narrative that makes the confusion very peculiar. Popper makes the formula “Co(x, z) & ¬Co(y, z) & p(x, z) < p(y, z)” appear all the more self-contradictory because he '''first''' defined p(x, z) > p(x) as the absolute form Co(x, z) (“z confirms x”) which resembles C(x, z). This is a case where the fallacy highly depends on the presentation using a mix of formal and natural discourse: introduce an abbrevation Co(x, z) that makes it easy to define in an informal and amnesic way (“z confirms x” which forgets the precise form of the inequality p(x, z) > p(x)), then inject that informal definition in the formula C(x, z) < C(y, z) to obtain the contradictory-looking informal statement “z confirms x to a lesser degree than z confirms y”: there you have a medium-specific narrative.


The contradictions kind of “stop” the text. Not that one is forced to stop reading. The usual way people reconcile contradictions with the undisturbed flow of the text is by conceiving them as a mosaic of good and bad points. In other words, we fill the “holes” of the fallacies with the holes that make up the mosaic.
The contradictions kind of “stop” the text. Not that one is forced to stop reading. The usual way people reconcile contradictions with the undisturbed flow of the text is by conceiving them as a mosaic of good and bad points. In other words, we fill the “holes” of the fallacies with the holes that make up the mosaic.
Line 402: Line 444:
|Psychanalyse et familialisme, in ''Anti-Œdipus''}}
|Psychanalyse et familialisme, in ''Anti-Œdipus''}}


The stopping does not only apply to contradictions, but also to a whole repertoire of attention-grabbers: writing style, subject matter… anything, really, that may lead to something as innocuous-looking as liking or disliking. In music, we may stop listening to a death metal song after just a few notes just because the Cookie Monster vocals put us off. We may not finish a book because we disagree with its main points, or find it hard to care about the characters, or are just getting bored by the first pages. But even a boring start may lead to a rewarding overall experience. This applies to other media as well. In visual art, contradictions take the form of confusion, e.g., confusion between the mundane and the sublime, the lively and the still, the planar and the perspective, the colorful and the monochromatic, the imitative and the non-imitative, etc. In a movie, we may take issue with something bad, distasteful, repulsive. Yet the movie continues unhindered. We are the Jean-François Lyotard that Deleuze and Guattari criticized for “never ceasing to stop the process, to recall the schizes to the shores that he just left, coded or overcoded territories, spaces and structures, where they only bring ‘transgressions,’ disorders and distortions that remain secondary nonetheless.”
The stopping does not only apply to contradictions, but also to a whole repertoire of attention-grabbers: writing style, subject matter… anything, really, that can be valued. In music, we may stop listening to a death metal song after just a few notes just because the Cookie Monster vocals put us off. We may not finish a book because we disagree with its main points, or find it hard to care about the characters, or are just getting bored by the first pages. But even a boring start may lead to a rewarding overall experience. This applies to other media as well. In visual art, contradictions take the form of confusion, e.g., confusion between the mundane and the sublime, the lively and the still, the planar and the perspective, the colorful and the monochromatic, the imitative and the non-imitative, etc. In a movie, we may take issue with something bad, distasteful, repulsive. Yet the movie continues to live its life. We are the Jean-François Lyotard that Deleuze and Guattari criticized for “never ceasing to stop the process, to recall the schizes to the shores that he just left, coded or overcoded territories, spaces and structures, where they only bring ‘transgressions,’ disorders and distortions that remain secondary nonetheless.”


{{quote|Learning to see—accustoming the eye to calmness, to patience, to letting things come up to it; postponing judgment, learning to go around and grasp each individual case from all sides. That is the first preliminary schooling for spirituality: not to react at once to a stimulus, but to gain control of all the inhibiting, excluding instincts. Learning to see, as I understand it, is almost what, unphilosophically speaking, is called a strong will: the essential feature is precisely not to “will”—to be able to suspend decision. All unspirituality, all vulgar commonness, depend on the inability to resist a stimulus: one must react, one follows every impulse. In many cases, such a compulsion is already pathology, decline, a symptom of exhaustion—almost everything that unphilosophical crudity designates with the word “vice” is merely this physiological inability not to react. A practical application of having learned to see: as a learner, one will have become altogether slow, mistrustful, recalcitrant. One will let strange, new things of every kind come up to oneself, inspecting them with hostile calm and withdrawing one’s hand. To have all doors standing open, to lie servilely on one’s stomach before every '''little fact''', always to be prepared for the leap of '''putting oneself into the place of, or of plunging into, others and other things'''—in short, the famous modern “objectivity”—is bad taste, is ignoble par excellence.
{{quote|Learning to see—accustoming the eye to calmness, to patience, to letting things come up to it; postponing judgment, learning to go around and grasp each individual case from all sides. That is the first preliminary schooling for spirituality: not to react at once to a stimulus, but to gain control of all the inhibiting, excluding instincts. Learning to see, as I understand it, is almost what, unphilosophically speaking, is called a strong will: the essential feature is precisely not to “will”—to be able to suspend decision. '''All unspirituality, all vulgar commonness, depend on the inability to resist a stimulus: one must react, one follows every impulse'''. In many cases, such a compulsion is already pathology, decline, a symptom of exhaustion—almost everything that unphilosophical crudity designates with the word “vice” is merely this physiological inability not to react. A practical application of having learned to see: as a learner, one will have become altogether slow, mistrustful, recalcitrant. One will let strange, new things of every kind come up to oneself, inspecting them with hostile calm and withdrawing one’s hand. To have all doors standing open, to lie servilely on one’s stomach '''before every little fact''', always to be prepared for the leap of putting oneself into the place of, or of plunging into, others and other things—in short, the famous modern “objectivity”—is bad taste, is ignoble par excellence.
|
|
|Friedrich Nietzsche
|Friedrich Nietzsche
Line 410: Line 452:
}}
}}


This discourse seems to echo the good old plea for open-mindedness. However, when people beg for open-mindedness, it is usually either in the hope of changing other people’s minds or with the mindset that others should have better tastes. In effect, the others are being criticized for their tastes, albeit in a politically correct way. “Be open-minded, what you don’t like is actually very good, you’ll see.” On the contrary, I absolutely don’t intend to change people’s minds about what they don’t like. What people didn’t like, they’ll still dislike, whatever it is they don’t like. I only speak from the perspective of the medium-specific narrative, which might very well be different from “what they don’t like,” although both are materially the same content. To use a metaphor: feces are distasteful and repulsive, a useless by-product (who would complain if we never had to defecate ever again?), yet this doesn’t take anything away from the elegance of a rural environment where one can defecate in the open and let Nature make it disappear in a matter of minutes, especially when compared to our artificial sewage systems.
This discourse seems to echo the good old plea for open-mindedness. However, when people beg for open-mindedness, it is usually either in the hope of changing other people’s minds or with the mindset that others should have better tastes. In effect, the others are being criticized for their tastes, albeit in a politically correct way. “Be open-minded, what you don’t like is actually very good, you’ll see.” On the contrary, I absolutely don’t intend to change people’s minds about what they don’t like. What people didn’t like, they’ll still dislike, whatever it is they don’t like. I only speak from the perspective of the medium-specific narrative, which might very well be different from “what they don’t like,” '''although both are materially the same content'''. To use a metaphor: feces are distasteful and repulsive, a useless by-product (who would complain if we never had to defecate ever again?), yet this doesn’t take anything away from the elegance of a rural environment where one can defecate in the open and let Nature make it disappear in a matter of minutes, especially when compared to our artificial sewage systems.


{{quote|Dung beetles play a remarkable role in agriculture. By burying and consuming dung, they improve nutrient recycling and soil structure. They also protect livestock, such as cattle, by removing the dung which, if left, could provide habitat for pests such as flies. Therefore, many countries have introduced the creatures for the benefit of animal husbandry. In developing countries, the beetles are especially important as an adjunct for improving standards of hygiene. The American Institute of Biological Sciences reports that dung beetles save the United States cattle industry an estimated US$380 million annually through burying above-ground livestock feces.
{{quote|Dung beetles play a remarkable role in agriculture. By burying and consuming dung, they improve nutrient recycling and soil structure. They also protect livestock, such as cattle, by removing the dung which, if left, could provide habitat for pests such as flies. Therefore, many countries have introduced the creatures for the benefit of animal husbandry. In developing countries, the beetles are especially important as an adjunct for improving standards of hygiene. The American Institute of Biological Sciences reports that dung beetles save the United States cattle industry an estimated US$380 million annually through burying above-ground livestock feces.
Line 437: Line 479:
}}
}}


For some, this would be cause enough for ditching modern physics. Non-Euclidean geometry is neither intuitive, nor observable, nor simple—for what would be a space where “parallel” lines intersect? However, the non-intuitive may lead to the prediction of observable effects. And it can also simplify theory:
For some, this would be cause enough for ditching modern physics. Non-Euclidean geometry is neither intuitive, nor observable, nor simple—for what would be a space where “parallel” lines intersect? However, the non-intuitive theories may lead to the prediction of observable effects. And non-intuitive concepts can simplify theory:


{{quote|Based on Henri Poincaré’s conventionalism, philosophers such as Pierre Duhem (1914) or Hugo Dingler (1920) argued that the classical concepts of space, time, and geometry were, and will always be, the most convenient expressions in natural science, therefore the concepts of relativity cannot be correct. This was criticized by proponents of logical positivism such as Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, or Reichenbach. They argued that Poincaré’s conventionalism could be modified, as to bring it into accord with relativity. Although it’s true, that the basis assumptions of Newtonian mechanics are more simple, it can only be brought into accord with modern experiments by inventing auxiliary hypotheses. On the other hand, '''relativity doesn’t need such hypotheses, thus from a conceptual viewpoint, relativity is in fact more simple than Newtonian mechanics'''.
{{quote|Based on Henri Poincaré’s conventionalism, philosophers such as Pierre Duhem (1914) or Hugo Dingler (1920) argued that the classical concepts of space, time, and geometry were, and will always be, the most convenient expressions in natural science, therefore the concepts of relativity cannot be correct. This was criticized by proponents of logical positivism such as Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, or Reichenbach. They argued that Poincaré’s conventionalism could be modified, as to bring it into accord with relativity. Although it’s true, that the basis assumptions of Newtonian mechanics are more simple, it can only be brought into accord with modern experiments by inventing auxiliary hypotheses. On the other hand, '''relativity doesn’t need such hypotheses, thus from a conceptual viewpoint, relativity is in fact more simple than Newtonian mechanics'''.
Line 449: Line 491:
=====Rediscovering philosophy=====
=====Rediscovering philosophy=====


Even if it’s not considered art, a philosophical work, as a text, has text-specific narratives. In a field where most problems originate from the definitions, the interpretation of a text-specific narrative has the tastefulness not to descend into the spiral of surmising with one’s definitions to prove one’s point. Instead, it reveals the uniqueness of the definitions.
Even if it’s not considered art, a philosophical work (or any written work in general) has text-specific narratives. In a field where most problems originate from the definitions, the interpretation of a text-specific narrative has the tastefulness not to descend into the spiral of surmising with different definitions to prove one’s point. Instead, it reveals the uniqueness of a thought process.


A point can be made that without its false problems from definitions, philosophy would be boring. Its arguments would either be perfectly logical to the point of tautology, or verge on the mystic. For example, the talk about objectivity and reality would dumb down to the assertion that “objects” are external to me in the sense of their spatial relationship to my body. Granted, it wouldn’t be as interesting as speculating of an external reality “in-itself,” lying outside my perception. This is the paradigm of the philosopher (here Descartes) who creates “interesting” false problems that keep the next generations of philosophers busy for nothing. Ironically, these critics, being philosophers themselves, can’t help but make what is bred in the bone come out in the flesh. So there are some cases where the critic is spot-on, but in their own philosophy walks into pretty much the same traps as their peers—cf. reconstructions of Schopenhauer tackling Leibniz and Hegel.
A point can be made that without its false problems , philosophy would be boring. Its arguments would either be perfectly logical to the point of tautology, or verge on the mystic. For example, the talk about objectivity and reality would dumb down to the assertion that “objects” are external to me in the sense of their spatial relationship to my body. Granted, it wouldn’t be as interesting as speculating of an external reality “in-itself,” lying outside my perception. This is the classic case of a philosopher who creates “interesting” false problems that keep the next generations of philosophers busy for nothing. Ironically, these critics, being philosophers themselves, can’t help but make what is bred in the bone come out in the flesh. So there are some cases where the critic is spot-on, but in their own philosophy walks into pretty much the same traps as their peers—cf. Schopenhauer tackling Leibniz or Hegel.


Definition issues are often supported by selective amnesia. For example, the author presupposes A to prove some statement (in favor of the author’s thesis), then presupposes the antithesis of A (amnesia of the thesis of A) to prove another statement. Amnesia can happen at all scopes. At the phrase and paragraph level, amnesia is a traditional literary style figure that is generally acknowledged by literary analysis. As the scope gets broader, analysis loses granularity and uniqueness.
Definition issues are often supported by selective amnesia. For example, the author presupposes A to prove some statement (in favor of the author’s thesis), then presupposes the antithesis of A (amnesia of the thesis of A) to prove another statement. Amnesia can happen at all scopes. At the phrase and paragraph level, amnesia can take the form of a traditional figure of speech. As the scope gets broader, amnesia takes more unique forms less acknowledged by academic literary analysis.


At the phrase level, take the infamous “DLC fiasco,” where a game editor, Capcom, delivers a game disc on the Playstation with locked content that can be unlocked for a fee. Then came the voices of protest:
At the phrase level, take the infamous “DLC fiasco,” where a game editor, Capcom, delivers a game disc on the Playstation with locked content that can be unlocked for a fee. Then came the voices of protest:
Line 463: Line 505:
}}
}}


But if “you just paid for a license,” then Capcom doesn’t revoke anything you paid for by locking away the content, since '''the lock is part of the license''', which is where amnesia struck. Of course, this doesn’t mean people don’t have the right to be discontent, but they can’t expect to be any more legit than someone protesting that a car should come with all the accessories because the manufacturer has the keys to unlock the warehouse.
But if “you just paid for a license,” then Capcom doesn’t revoke anything you paid for by locking away the content, since '''the lock is part of the license''', which is where amnesia struck. Of course, this doesn’t mean people don’t have the right to be discontent, but they can’t expect to be any more legit than someone protesting that a car should come with all the accessories because the manufacturer has the keys to the warehouse.


At the paragraph level, in ''Anti-Œdipus'' Deleuze and Guattari take a bite at Freud’s Œdipus complex. In particular, they argue that incest is impossible in the system in which it exists:
At the paragraph level, in ''Anti-Œdipus'' Deleuze and Guattari take a bite at Freud’s Œdipus complex. In particular, they argue that incest is impossible in the system in which it exists:


{{quote|[…] the names, the appellations no longer designate intensive states, but discernible persons. '''Discernibility settles on the sister and the mother as prohibited spouses.''' The reason is that persons, with the names that now designate them, do not exist prior to the prohibitions as spouses. Robert Jaulin says it well: “The mythical discourse has as its theme the passage from the indifference to incest to its prohibition. Implicit or explicit, this theme underlies all the myths; it is therefore a formal property of this language.” We must conclude that, strictly speaking, incest does not and cannot exist. We are always on this side of incest, in a series of intensities that is ignorant of discernible persons; or else beyond incest, in an extension that recognizes them, that constitutes them, but that does not constitute them without making them '''impossible''' as sexual partners. One can commit incest only after a series of substitutions that always moves us away from it, that is to say, with a person who is equivalent to the mother or the sister only by virtue of being neither: she who is '''discernible as a possible spouse'''.
{{quote|[…] the names, the appellations no longer designate intensive states, but discernible persons. '''Discernibility settles on the sister and the mother as prohibited spouses.''' The reason is that persons, with the names that now designate them, do not exist prior to the prohibitions as spouses. Robert Jaulin says it well: “The mythical discourse has as its theme the passage from the indifference to incest to its prohibition. Implicit or explicit, this theme underlies all the myths; it is therefore a formal property of this language.” '''We must conclude that, strictly speaking, incest does not and cannot exist'''. We are always on this side of incest, in a series of intensities that is ignorant of discernible persons; or else beyond incest, in an extension that recognizes them, that constitutes them, but that does not constitute them without making them '''impossible''' as sexual partners. One can commit incest only after a series of substitutions that always moves us away from it, that is to say, with a person who is equivalent to the mother or the sister only by virtue of being neither: she who is '''discernible as a possible spouse'''.
|[…] les noms ,les appellations ne désignent plus des états intensifs, mais des personnes discernables. '''La discernabilité se pose sur la sœur, la mère comme épouses interdites.''' C’est que les personnes , avec les noms qui les désignent maintenant, ne préexistent pas aux interdits qui les constituent comme telles. Mère et sœur ne préexistent pas à leur interdiction comme épouses. Robert Jaulin le dit très bien: “Le discours mythique a pour thème le passage de l’indifférence à l’inceste à sa prohibition : implicite ou explicite, ce thème est sous-jacent à tous les mythes ; il est donc une propriété formelle de ce langage.” De l’inceste, il faut conclure à la lettre qu’il n’existe pas, ne peut pas exister. L’inceste, on est toujours en deçà, dans une série d’intensités qui ignore les personnes discernables ; ou bien au-delà, dans une extension qui les reconnaît, qui les constitue, mais qui ne les constitue pas sans les rendre impossibles comme partenaires sexuels. L’inceste, on ne peut le faire qu’à la suite d’une série de substitutions qui nous en éloigne toujours, c’est-à-dire avec une personne qui ne vaut pour la mère ou la sœur qu’à force de ne pas l’être : celle qui est '''discernable comme épouse possible'''.
|[…] les noms, les appellations ne désignent plus des états intensifs, mais des personnes discernables. '''La discernabilité se pose sur la sœur, la mère comme épouses interdites.''' C’est que les personnes, avec les noms qui les désignent maintenant, ne préexistent pas aux interdits qui les constituent comme telles. Mère et sœur ne préexistent pas à leur interdiction comme épouses. Robert Jaulin le dit très bien: “Le discours mythique a pour thème le passage de l’indifférence à l’inceste à sa prohibition : implicite ou explicite, ce thème est sous-jacent à tous les mythes; il est donc une propriété formelle de ce langage.” De l’inceste, il faut conclure à la lettre qu’il n’existe pas, ne peut pas exister. L’inceste, on est toujours en deçà, dans une série d’intensités qui ignore les personnes discernables; ou bien au-delà, dans une extension qui les reconnaît, qui les constitue, mais qui ne les constitue pas sans les rendre impossibles comme partenaires sexuels. L’inceste, on ne peut le faire qu’à la suite d’une série de substitutions qui nous en éloigne toujours, c’est-à-dire avec une personne qui ne vaut pour la mère ou la sœur qu’à force de ne pas l’être: celle qui est '''discernable comme épouse possible'''.
|
|
|Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari
|Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari
Line 474: Line 516:
}}
}}


“Prohibited spouse” was sneakily replaced by “impossible spouse,” so that, indeed, it is now impossible to commit incest, since, '''by definition''', incest now identifies mother and sister as impossible.
In the quoted paragraph, “prohibited spouse” was replaced by “impossible spouse,” so that, indeed, it is now impossible to commit incest, since, '''by definition''', incest now identifies mother and sister as impossible spouses—i.e., having sex with a woman makes her non-mother and non-sister, by definition.


In ''The Capital'', Karl Marx demonstrates the laborer’s contribution to increased production:
In ''The Capital'', Karl Marx demonstrates the laborer’s contribution to increased production:
Line 484: Line 526:
}}
}}


Here the “advance of [more seed and manure] is made,” but in the concluding phrase of the paragraph, the increased production now occurs “without the intervention of any new capital.” This rhetorical trick allows Marx to make the labourers shine.
Here the “advance of [more seed and manure] is made,” but in the concluding phrase of the paragraph, the increased production now occurs “without the intervention of any new capital.” This rhetorical trick allows Marx to make the labourers steal the show.


Gottlob Frege’s ''the Foundations of Arithmetic'' offers a good example of book-level amnesia. It enters a particular category, that of not keeping a promise made at the beginning of a book. The book starts with this:
Gottlob Frege’s ''the Foundations of Arithmetic'' offers a good example of book-level amnesia. It enters a particular category, that of not keeping a promise made at the beginning of a book. The book starts with this:
Line 502: Line 544:
}}
}}


Therefore Frege’s definition relies on an “indefinite” (the “extension of concept”) “without stating which thing it is”, and thus ends up doing what he warned not to do.
Therefore Frege’s Number relies on an “indefinite” (the “extension of concept”), and thus ends up doing what he warned not to do (not “stating which thing it is”).


===Rediscovering repetition===
===Rediscovering repetition===


Repetition is a significant concept of artistic expression. The trope of the story loop, where the ending reflects the beginning, is quite common, from literature (e.g., Lewis Carrol’s ''Alice In Wonderland'') to video games (e.g., ''The Last of Us'', where the main protagonist carries to safety a girl the same way he carried his late daughter at the start of the game). In poetry, repetition of sound and structure has been thoroughly studied. Repetition is also a well-known comedic device.
Repetition is a significant tool of artistic expression. For example, the trope of the story loop, where the ending reflects the beginning, is quite common, from literature (e.g., Lewis Carrol’s ''Alice In Wonderland'') to video games (e.g., ''The Last of Us'', where the main protagonist carries to safety a girl the same way he carried his late daughter at the start of the game). In poetry, repetition of sound and structure has been thoroughly studied. Repetition is also a well-known comedic device—e.g., Monty Python’s ''Déjà Vu'' sketch.


{{quote|The polypoids were burning in the wood
<div style="white-space: pre;">{{quote|The polypoids were burning in the wood
A stone caught fire
A stone caught fire
The castle caught fire
The castle caught fire
Line 525: Line 567:
||Eugène Ionesco
||Eugène Ionesco
|''The Bald Soprano''
|''The Bald Soprano''
}}
}}</div>


The concept of repetition usually serves the purpose of establishing tropes and categories. So although it is fundamentally a temporal concept, it compresses and abstracts time, and as a result loses the medium-specific narratives. For example, in classical music, one is used to designate or identify the sections of a concerto or symphony by a “blanket tempo.A Vivaldi concerto, for example, is often divided into 3 movements identified by the tempo, usually: ''Allegro'' (fast), ''Largo'' (slow), then ''Allegro'' (fast). Each movement’s velocity is never as strictly uniform as the tempo would suggest. It’s like velocity had been made into an atemporal category by abstracting away the velocity changes inside the movements.
As a result, the concept of repetition is commonly known as a trope. So although it is fundamentally a temporal concept, it seems to compress and abstract time. Same with the concept of tempo. In classical music, one is used to designate the sections of a concerto or symphony by a blanket tempo. A Vivaldi concerto, for example, is often divided into 3 movements identified by the tempo, usually: ''Allegro'' (fast), ''Largo'' (slow), then ''Allegro'' (fast). Each movement’s velocity is never as strictly uniform as the tempo would suggest. It’s as if velocity had been made into an atemporal category by abstracting away the velocity changes inside the movements.


Blanket concepts are a product of medium-specific narratives becoming easily identifiable and well-known concepts. On the other hand, the more unique the narrative, the less blanketable it becomes. For example, the aforementioned medium-specific narrative of ''Ode to a Grecian Urn'' doesn’t have (yet) a blanket term because it is fairly specific, although each step of the narrative is individually unremarkable. Some steps are a simple repetition, but they become specific in the context of a narrative. As a consequence of its specificity, the whole medium-specific narrative can only be communicated by going through all its steps in order, recreating a temporal structure.
Blanket concepts are a product of abstracting the medium-specific narratives into easily identifiable and well-known concepts. On the other hand, the more unique and granular the narrative, the less blanketable it becomes. For example, the aforementioned medium-specific narrative of ''Ode on a Grecian Urn'' doesn’t have (yet) a blanket term because it is fairly specific, although each step of the narrative is individually unremarkable. Some steps are a simple repetition, but are specific to the enclosing narrative. As a consequence of its specificity, the whole medium-specific narrative can only be communicated by going through all its steps in order, re-emphasizing the temporality of the structure.


Yet, blanket concepts sometimes pretend to capture uniqueness. For example, a music theory class may characterize Chopin’s music by its “question/answer structures.” That is, the phrases played in succession on the piano almost sound like a dialogue between different instruments. But, come to think of it, one can actually say the same thing of any piece of music. It’s not only the phrases that engage into a dialogue. A phrase can be divided into segments that compete to make their individual voices heard. Division is recursive and can reach down to the notes. The levels of division don’t have to be mutually exclusive; so smaller segments can enter into a dialogue with larger segments. The particular way in which a dialogue takes life is a medium-specific narrative, but the “question/answer structures” are such a broad description that they end up defeating the basic purpose of medium-specific narratives (which is to be specific).
Yet, blanket concepts sometimes pretend to capture uniqueness. For example, a music theory class may characterize Chopin’s music by its “question/answer structures.” The phrases played in succession on the piano almost sound like a dialogue between different instruments. But, come to think of it, one can actually say the same thing of any piece of music. It’s not only the phrases that engage into a dialogue. A phrase is divided into segments that compete to make their individual voices heard. Division is recursive and can reach down to the notes. The levels of division don’t have to be mutually exclusive; so smaller segments can enter into a dialogue with larger segments. The particular way in which a dialogue takes life is a medium-specific narrative, but the “question/answer structures” are such a broad description that they end up defeating the basic purpose of medium-specific narratives (which is to be specific).


Unique uses of repetition in medium-specific narratives cannot be described by blanket concepts. For example, William Faulkner’s ''A Light in August'' starts with a pregnant woman named Lena, on a quest to find her child’s father:
Unique uses of repetition in medium-specific narratives cannot be described by blanket concepts. For example, William Faulkner’s ''A Light in August'' starts with a pregnant woman named Lena, on a quest to find her child’s father:
Line 540: Line 582:
}}
}}


The first chapter ends with the following:
The first chapter ends with the following lines:


{{quote|“My, my,” she say; “here I aint been on the road but four weeks, and now I am in Jefferson already. My, my. A body does get around.”
{{quote|“My, my,” she say; “here I aint been on the road but four weeks, and now I am in Jefferson already. My, my. A body does get around.”
Line 554: Line 596:
}}
}}


But the repetition highlights two changes in particular: her destination (Tennessee instead of Jefferson) and the transition from “'''I''' have come from Alabama […] I aint been on the road but four weeks” to “'''we''' aint been coming from Alabama but two months,” as she gave birth halfway through the book. The discovery of this indifference toward the destination since the beginning of the book (“I think she was just travelling. I dont think she had any idea of finding whoever it was she was following”) recontextualizes all that happens in-between the repeated bits (so the whole book, basically), as the birth wreaks havoc in the lives of all the main characters, except “we”—Lena and the baby, who get the smoothest ride of all (“she had got along all right this far, with folks taking good care of her”).
The repetition highlights two changes in particular: her destination (Tennessee instead of Jefferson) and the transition from “'''I''' have come from Alabama […] I aint been on the road but four weeks” to “'''we''' aint been coming from Alabama but two months,” as she gave birth halfway through the book. The discovery of this indifference toward the destination since the beginning of the book (“I think she was just travelling. I dont think she had any idea of finding whoever it was she was following”) recontextualizes all that happens in-between the repeated bits (so the whole book, basically), as the reader realizes that the birth did wreak havoc in the lives of all the main characters, except “we”—Lena and the baby, who get the smoothest ride of all (“she had got along all right this far, with folks taking good care of her”).


The use of repetition to highlight a detail also underlies a medium-specific narrative of Yasmina Reza’s ''Dans la luge d’Arthur Schopenhauer''. This time, the repetition is contained in a single sentence, the last one in the book.
The use of repetition to highlight a detail also underlies a medium-specific narrative of Yasmina Reza’s ''Dans la luge d’Arthur Schopenhauer''. This time, the repetition is contained in a single sentence, the last one in the book.


{{quote|
{{quote|A woman gets up on the right foot, she goes out, she leaves for the day on the right foot, […] when suddenly she gets slowed by the body of another woman, […] we don’t want to stand in solidarity with the woman with the bags, we want to walk fast, we want to hit the ground with a bouncing step, walk without mercy, we don’t intend to turn around until the moment we turn around to see the face, fatal mistake, […] it’s a minor turnaround, which doesn’t involve the body, even though, facing her, as I said, we must fight against a stirring of the soul, unsolicited, a violent regret for something vague […] so I pause before the window display of a shoe store before which I always pause, in this shop window there’s enough to make my mood change drastically, see, I believe in frivolity, we’re fortunate to have frivolity, frivolity saves us, I’m surprised you don’t understand the superiority that we have of being saved by frivolity, the day frivolity lets us down we die, once a man said to me, about a dress that I had an eye on, the dress can wait, can wait what, I told him, until the body can’t get dressed anymore, until it’s my turn to clutter up the street, […] seeing her get closer to the shop window I thought once she was playing on the sidewalk, she was drawing a court, she was moving the lagger on one leg, '''she was hopping from square to square, she was hopping from square to square in her ballooning dress'''…
||Yasmina Reza
|Une femme se lève d’un bon pied, elle sort, elle s’en va dans la journée d’un bon pied, […] quand elle se trouve soudain empêchée par le corps d’une autre, […] nous ne voulons pas être solidaire de la femme aux sacs, nous voulons marcher vite, nous voulons attaquer le sol d’un pied bondissant, marcher sans aucune pitié, nous n’avons pas l’intention de nous retourner jusqu’au moment où nous nous retournons pour voir le visage, une erreur fatale, […] c’est un retournement mineur, qui n’engage pas le corps, bien que de face disais-je, alors que nous sommes déjà loin, il faille lutter contre une flexion de l’âme, survenue malgré soi, un regret violent dont l’objet reste flou, […] alors je m’arrête devant la vitrine du magasin de chaussures devant lequel toujours je m’arrête, dans cette vitrine il y a de quoi me faire changer radicalement d’humeur, je crois voyez-vous à la frivolité, heureusement que nous avons la frivolité, la frivolité nous sauve, je suis étonnée que vous ne compreniez pas cette supériorité que nous avons d’être sauvées par la frivolité, le jour où la frivolité nous abandonne nous mourons, une fois un homme m’a dit, à propos d’une robe que j’avais repérée, la robe peut attendre, peut attendre quoi ai-je rétorqué, que le corps soit inhabillable, que j’encombre la rue à mon tour, […] en la voyant s’approcher de la vitrine j’ai pensé un jour elle s’amusait sur le trottoir, elle dessinait une marelle, elle poussait le palet à cloche-pied, '''elle sautait les cases, elle sautait les cases dans sa jupe gonflée'''…|Yasmina Reza
|''On Arthur Schopenhauer’s Sledge''
|''On Arthur Schopenhauer’s Sledge''
}}
}}


On both ''On Arthur Schopenhauer’s Sledge'' and ''A Light in August'', repetition is used in a unique medium-specific way that eludes tropes and blanket concepts. Obviousness, especially in regard to the strategic placement in the concluding lines, is needed to attract attention to book-level narratives which could easily get overlooked otherwise.
The repetition in the last line makes the detail of the “ballooning dress” stand out. It is the finishing touch of a metaphor synthesizing themes developed in the previous chapters: the theme of turning around, the theme of coming back, as the old woman with the bags catches up to the relentless woman, and the “frivolity” of clothing details.
 
On both ''On Arthur Schopenhauer’s Sledge'' and ''A Light in August'', repetition is used in a unique medium-specific way that eludes tropes and blanket concepts. The blatantness of repetition, especially in conjunction with the strategic placement (in the concluding lines of a chapter or the whole book), is able to attract attention to details of narratives which would easily get overlooked otherwise.


===Rediscovering composite media===
===Rediscovering composite media===
Line 569: Line 613:
====Intra-medium narrative versus composite media such as songs. “Medium pairing” as a value judgment versus the intra-heteromedium narrative.====
====Intra-medium narrative versus composite media such as songs. “Medium pairing” as a value judgment versus the intra-heteromedium narrative.====


The notions of medium specificity and of being intra-medium bring up the question “Which medium?” A composite medium is a combination of layers, e.g., a song can be seen as lyrics on top of an instrumental. I will use the term “heteromedium” for such media, and “intra-heteromedium” to qualify an interpretation limited to the content of a heteromedium.
The notions of medium specificity and of being intra-medium bring up the question “Which medium?” A composite medium is a combination of layers, e.g., a song can be seen as lyrics on top of an instrumental. I will use the term “heteromedium” when emphasizing this compositeness, and “intra-heteromedium” to qualify an interpretation limited to the content of a heteromedium.


To be perfectly accurate, what most would consider to be a monomedium is necessarily composite. Text has sound, syntax, semantics, structure, etc. Sound has tonality, rhythm, phrasing, texture, etc. Furthermore, not one such property can be made into a “truly” one-dimensional medium. Tonality cannot exist in a vacuum, just like color cannot exist without some sense of shape, or a line without some sense of thickness. Even so, we never pay attention to everything. It is not uncommon to ignore the lyrics in a song. Other parts of the medium may be deemed unessential depending on the listener. When listening to a heavy metal song, I will usually ignore the obligatory guitar solo every other chorus, the elaborate drum fills, redundant bass lines, etc.
To be perfectly accurate, what most would consider to be a monomedium is necessarily composite. Text has sound, syntax, semantics, structure, etc. Sound has tonality, rhythm, phrasing, texture, etc. Furthermore, not one such property can be made into a “truly” one-dimensional medium. Tonality cannot exist in a vacuum, just like color cannot exist without some sense of shape, or a line without some sense of thickness. Even so, we never pay attention to everything. It is not uncommon to ignore the lyrics in a song. Other parts of the medium may be deemed unessential depending on the listener. When listening to a heavy metal song, I will usually ignore the obligatory guitar solo every other chorus, the elaborate drum fills, redundant bass lines, etc.


Despite the fundamental heterogeneity of heteromedia, there has always been a sense of medium unity which has overpowered the other aspects of heteromedium interpretation. It is not uncommon to hear about how well lyrics match the music, the music the movie, the dancing the music, etc. The question as to how well the layers match is typically indicative of a value judgment. But as with all value judgments, even if there is objectivity in the match—e.g., rhythmic and mood affinity between dance and music—the accompanying value judgment is fundamentally questionable. Nothing says that only positive affinity is necessary to make a “great” match. One could argue that happy lyrics go with dark music as a spooky combination—think porcelain doll in the dark—or as a spoof. On the other hand, dark lyrics over dark music can be of great comedic value if taken too seriously by thei, for example satanic music in a world where Christianity has become irrelevant. What is taken seriously by some is derided by others. The song ''Black Sabbath'' may be taken seriously by “true heavy metal” fans and Satan-fearing parents, while others laugh off the cheesy horror lyrics. The fundamental separation between the evil theme and metal as “evil music” is such that people could invent the genre of “white metal,” i.e., Christ-hailing metal, and you can be sure that this genre has its legion of fans who swear by it alone. In any case, celebrating evil or god in songs is and has always been as deridable as your next self-proclaimed black metal misanthropes touring the world to meet their fans.
Despite the fundamental heterogeneity of every medium, there has always been a sense of medium unity which has overpowered the other aspects of heteromedium interpretation. It is not uncommon to hear about how well lyrics match the music, the music the movie, the dancing the music, etc. The question as to how well the layers match is typically indicative of a value judgment. But as with all value judgments, even if there is objectivity in the match—e.g., rhythmic affinity between dance and music—the accompanying value judgment is fundamentally questionable. Nothing says that only positive affinity is necessary to make a “great” match. One could argue that happy lyrics go with dark music as a spooky combination—think porcelain doll in the dark—or as a spoof. On the other hand, dark lyrics over dark music can be of great comedic value if taken too seriously, for example satanic music in a world where Christianity has become irrelevant. What is taken seriously by some is easily derided by others. The song ''Black Sabbath'' may be taken seriously by “true heavy metal” fans and Satan-fearing parents, while others laugh off the cheesy horror lyrics. The fundamental separation between the evil theme and metal music is such that people could invent the genre of “white metal,” i.e., Christ-hailing metal. In any case, celebrating evil or god in songs is and has always been as deridable as the average self-proclaimed black metal misanthropes touring the world to party with their fans while promoting their latest album.


The act of viewing a medium as a composite medium for the purposes of value judgments, “medium pairing,” is not to be mistaken with the interpretation of a heteromedium-specific narrative. Narratives are about change, which statements on fitness for purpose (“the costumes fit the theme so well!”) are not. So when one talks of “medium-specific narrative,” one considers '''changes across the medium pairing''', not the pairing itself. Typically, the medium-specific narrative of a song (to mind: not album, not artist, but the individual song itself) focuses on melody, not style, genre, technique, or production (all invariants with respect to the narrative), and only deals with harmony insofar it partakes in producing melody. The purely musical narrative is in most cases tangent to the lyrics, although one can always try to look for narratives from the '''coupling of''' music '''with''' lyrics (rather than the '''meaning of''' music '''in''' lyrics, or the meaning of music in emotion), just as comics combine drawings with text into a particular type of narrative material, as was seen with ''Touti and his Exhaust Pipe''.
The act of viewing a medium as a composite medium for the purposes of value judgments, “medium pairing,” is not to be mistaken with the interpretation of a heteromedium-specific narrative. Narratives are about change, which statements on fitness for purpose (“the costumes fit the medieval fantasy theme so well!”) are not. So when one talks of “medium-specific narrative,” one considers '''changes across the medium pairing''', not the pairing itself. Typically, the medium-specific narrative of a song (to mind: not album, not artist, but the individual song itself) focuses on melody, not style, genre, technique, or production (all invariants with respect to the narrative), and only deals with harmony insofar it partakes in producing melody. The purely musical narrative is usually tangent to the lyrics, although one can always try to look for narratives from the '''coupling of''' music '''with''' lyrics (rather than the '''meaning of''' music '''in''' lyrics, or the meaning of music in emotion), just like comics combine drawings and text into a particular type of narrative material, as was seen with ''Touti and his Exhaust Pipe''.




{{book}}
{{book}}

Latest revision as of 23:52, 5 December 2021

This page is part of a book

Interpretation of the medium-specific narrative

The alternative to the interpretation of the average value is what, in the absence of a more marketable expression, I call the “interpretation of the medium-specific narrative.” The medium-specific narratives are the opposite of the mosaics. Instead of a loose whole, one searches for some tightly-knit structure, with all extras removed. A work contains many medium-specific narratives that may overlap. There may not even be a “the one” medium-specific narrative that the creator is supposed to have designed and intended for their audience. The existence of “the one” is best left to speculative (and ultimately sterile) endeavours. Some narrative may look like it, but in general, the medium-specific narratives are modest in scope and fundamentally hedonistic: the satisfaction of finding one is purely subjective.

The expression “interpretation of the medium-specific narrative” (non-plural) as used in this essay is somewhat misleading. It actually means an interpretation that reveals one of the medium-specific narratives of the interpreted content. You can think of “the medium-specific narrative” as the content itself, and the “interpretation” as a medium-specific sub-narrative that results from a filtering of “the medium-specifc narrative”.

The medium-specific narrative as a narrative of elements related to each other due to the nature of the medium. The interpretation of the average value as a juxtaposition of disparate elements. Proximity of the medium-specific narrative to the content as a timeline of events that actually happen to the consumer. The interpretation of the medium-specific narrative is essentially a rendering of a medium-specific narrative, with an implicit non-committal value judgment that doesn’t detract from objectivity.

Narrative interpretation is an endeavor to view a work as, broadly speaking, a “story,” i.e., every element in the work is viewed in light of previous elements, the premises or context. If the elements form a succession of events in the same timeline, characters, locations, etc., then we recognize the traditional concept of story. But if the elements are the regions of a painting or the motifs of a musical piece, the concepts of “story” and “premise” take on a peculiar quality relative to the nature of the medium. In a pop song, an element could be a section, for example the chorus, and its premise could be the verse. Depending on the merits of doing so, one could look at a more granular level where an element could mean a phrase, the segment of a phrase, or even a note. Such an element can be seen as the premise to any other element that follows it in the song. In a painting, an “element” could, for example, mean a painted region, an object, or a motif. The concept of “premise” here can be somewhat misleading, as there isn’t a declared timeline. In this case, I like to generalize the definition of “premise” to mean “another element of the painting” which both gives it context and is given a context by it, depending on which element you view as the premise. The elements of a painting implicitly bond together through an implicit timeline, which is the timeline of the viewing experience. The movement of the viewer’s gaze from one region of the painting to another creates a subjective timeline of perceptions, a “story” of perceptions. This timeline tends to be ignored because the observer tends to compress it during the cognitive process—e.g., when we see a portrait, we recognize the face almost instantaneously, without going over the facial features individually. We’ll later see how this “photographic memory” can prejudice visual media.

The physical frame of the narrative (the canvas, the pages, or the sound track) is a convention. It narrows the search for narratives. But you could imagine looking for (and finding) medium-specific narratives in Nature or in any unintended arrangement of objects. This has important ramifications for how one looks at conventional art. The focus is now on the perceptions as they happen to the observer, not as they are intended by some intelligent being. In fact, the medium-specific narratives don’t refer to an external intelligent being at all, since it is outside the medium. On the other hand, a mosaic is the result when one talks of such an intelligent being, a Creator or Artist, in relation to the work.

The “medium specificity” of the narrative means that the elements of the narrative are homogeneous parts of the same medium. In other words, the narrative stays intra-medium. It is an interpretation of a content as a self-contained unit, filtering perceptions happening on a closed timeline (not the timeline of a story in the traditional sense). As a medium-specific narrative, a song is a succession of perceptions (melodies, harmonies, notes, and so on) and nothing else. By contrast, the interpretation of the average value results in a mosaic of features, including mood, theme, genre, and so on. Therefore, the listener first experiences the elements of medium-specific narratives. Considerations like theme or genre are high-level interpretations of these elements.

The mosaic as the medium-specific narrative of reviews

The interpretation of the average value reveals itself when one begins to analyze reviews, and more particularly their narrative structure (or rather the lack thereof), rather than just their supposed usefulness. In a way, reviews are works about works, using a stylistically distinctive thought process that builds upon content through an amnesic process. As such, the reviews have their own medium-specific narratives, of which the mosaic is the invariant. We saw an example through the interpretation of a modern art review.

More generally, medium-specific narratives are not confined to art. In terms of methodology, their interpretation doesn’t make any distinction between art and science, between fiction and non-fiction, between review and reviewed content. In fact, most critiques and analyses you will find in this text are interpretations of the medium-specific narratives of various papers, books, discourses, reviews, and everyday chatter. The interpretations are presented rather informally for the ease of reading, while staying recognizable by the characteristic minuteness with which they capture medium-specific intricacies.

A medium-specific narrative from John Keats’ Ode on a Grecian Urn. Interpretation writing styles

I chose John Keats’ Ode on a Grecian Urn because it is short and well-established in academic circles.

 Thou still unravish’d bride of quietness,

Thou foster-child of silence and slow time, Sylvan historian, who canst thus express A flowery tale more sweetly than our rhyme: What leaf-fring’d legend haunts about thy shape Of deities or mortals, or of both, In Tempe or the dales of Arcady? What men or gods are these? What maidens loth? What mad pursuit? What struggle to escape? What pipes and timbrels? What wild ecstasy?

Heard melodies are sweet, but those unheard Are sweeter; therefore, ye soft pipes, play on; Not to the sensual ear, but, more endear’d, Pipe to the spirit ditties of no tone: Fair youth, beneath the trees, thou canst not leave Thy song, nor ever can those trees be bare; Bold Lover, never, never canst thou kiss, Though winning near the goal yet, do not grieve; She cannot fade, though thou hast not thy bliss, For ever wilt thou love, and she be fair!

Ah, happy, happy boughs! that cannot shed Your leaves, nor ever bid the Spring adieu; And, happy melodist, unwearied, For ever piping songs for ever new; More happy love! more happy, happy love! For ever warm and still to be enjoy’d, For ever panting, and for ever young; All breathing human passion far above, That leaves a heart high-sorrowful and cloy’d, A burning forehead, and a parching tongue.

Who are these coming to the sacrifice? To what green altar, O mysterious priest, Lead’st thou that heifer lowing at the skies, And all her silken flanks with garlands drest? What little town by river or sea shore, Or mountain-built with peaceful citadel, Is emptied of this folk, this pious morn? And, little town, thy streets for evermore Will silent be; and not a soul to tell Why thou art desolate, can e’er return.

O Attic shape! Fair attitude! with brede Of marble men and maidens overwrought, With forest branches and the trodden weed; Thou, silent form, dost tease us out of thought As doth eternity: Cold Pastoral! When old age shall this generation waste, Thou shalt remain, in midst of other woe Than ours, a friend to man, to whom thou say’st, “Beauty is truth, truth beauty,—that is all

Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.” 
John Keats
Ode on a Grecian Urn

When I look for a medium-specific narrative, I try to find one that roughly covers the whole work, one that justifies the work as a unit. Here’s one:

  1. The narrator questions a silent “thou.”
  2. The narrator associates the silent (“those unheard are sweeter”) with the eternal (“canst not leave […] nor ever,” “never, never”, “For ever,” etc.).
  3. The eternal is then associated with repetitions of “happy” framed between assonant words (“Ah, happy, happy boughs!”, “More happy love! more happy, happy love!”).
  4. Finally, when the eternally silent (“Thou, silent form, dost tease us out of thought as doth eternity”) says something, it addresses the narrator’s questioning (“all ye need to know”) through structures of repetiton, reminiscent of the framed repetitions of “happy”: “Beauty is truth, truth beauty, that is all ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.”

All the terms of the interpretations are reused and combined in different contexts. In (1), the “silent thou” is asked questions which are addressed in (4). The repetitions of the answer “beauty is truth, truth beauty” echo the repetitions of the words happy and love in (3), but in a non-silent context which contrasts the silence in (1) and (2). A narrative thus emerges.

This narrative is medium-specific in the sense that it takes elements directly from the poem with almost no recourse to subjective interpretation. I say almost, because there is certainly some layer of interpretation there. I did skip many details, even entire parts of the poem. I also didn’t mention the stanza structure or the rhyme schemes. Implicit in these oversights is an assessment that they weren’t needed in the narrative I wanted to highlight. If you study the stanza structure or the poem’s themes, as most scholars do, you get invariants rather than a narrative. But this choice, to prefer this poem-wide narrative over invariants, is already an act of subjective interpretation, even if, in the last analysis, I just highlighted certain passages of the poem and their relationships.

I could cook the interpretation a little bit, as it is a little too raw as it is. I could add some commentary that would express the feelings and value judgments that led me to this narrative. I could say this:

« John Keats thus makes us realize that our questionings are superfluous, in the sense that the answer was already implied in the narrator’s enthusiastic exuberance. The answer is in the rythmic expressivity—whether in the questioning itself (the series of “what”) or in the insistence on eternity, happiness and love—that seems to anticipate T.S. Eliot’s criticism of the “grammatically meaningless” statement that “beauty is truth, truth beauty.” »

I will usually choose to stay away from this style of writing, but this is a purely personal choice. I personally like to address an audience that doesn’t need to be spoon-fed and will arrive at its own conclusions. In fact, I would argue that the raw interpretation doesn’t need any conclusion. The elements of the narrative are interlinked with one another in such a way that the whole point is lost as soon as one tries to wrap things up in a generic conclusion—i.e., the narrative is self-contained and self-conclusive, somewhat like “beauty is truth, truth beauty” is self-contained and self-conclusive. In fact, any type of value-based conclusion would attract the sort of (rightful) criticism against awkward attempts at penetrating non-objective concepts through objective interpretation—cf. Derrida’s criticism of Jean Rousset who tried to describe passion in literature (or at least invite his readers to sense it) using only geometrical concepts like “rings,” “symmetry,” “helices,” and so on:

 At the start of the essay Polyeucte or The Ring and the Helix, the author cautiously warns us that, if he insists upon “schemas that might seem excessively geometrical, it’s because Corneille, more than any other, practiced symmetries.” Moreover “this geometry is not cultivated for itself,” “it is in the great plays a means subordinated to passionate ends.”

But what does this essay actually tell us? Only the geometry of a theater which is, however, “that of the mad passion, of the heroic enthusiasm.” Not only does the geometrical structure of Polyeucte mobilize all the resources and attention of the author, but the whole teleology of Corneille’s trajectory is attached to it.

 
 Au début de l’essai intitulé Polyeucte ou la bouche et la vrille, l’auteur prévient prudemment que, s’il insiste sur “des schèmes qui peuvent paraître excessivement géométriques, c’est que Corneille, plus que tout autre, a a pratiqué les symétrie”. De plus “cette géométrie n’est pas cultivée pour elle-même”, “elle est dans les grandes pièces un moyen subordonné à des fins passionnelles”.

Mais que nous livre en fait cet essai? La seule géométrie d’un théâtre qui est pourtant “celui de la passion folle, de l’enthousiasme héroïque”. Non seulement la structure géométrique de Polyeucte mobilise toutes les ressources et toute l’attention de l’auteur, mais à elle est ordonnée toute une téléologie de l’itinéraire cornélien.

 
Jacques Derrida
Force and Signification, in Writing and Difference

Rediscovering intra-medium movement

Rediscovering intra-visuality. Restoring the primacy of the viewing angle.

Keeping the interpretation intra-medium is counter-intuitive to most of us. “This painting represents the king”: this is a very natural statement to read, though it is hardly concerned with the objective content. If the reader of the statement sticks to what the interpretation actually communicates, and tries to visualize a painting entirely through it, they would imagine a king sitting on a throne, a crown, maybe a heraldic symbol. The visuals, along with all the non-visual facts (including the fact that the king is represented), contribute a “story” that goes beyond the mere visuals.

 The Equestrian Portrait of Charles I (also known as Charles I on Horseback) is an oil painting on canvas by Anthony van Dyck, showing Charles I on horseback. Charles I had become King of Great Britain and Ireland in 1625 on the death of his father James I, and Van Dyck became the Charles’ Principal Painter in Ordinary in 1632. This portrait is thought to have been painted in about 1637–38, only a few years before the English Civil War broke out in 1642. It is one of many portraits of Charles by Van Dyck, including several equestrian portraits. 
English Wikipedia
Equestrian Portrait of Charles I

Such stories are independent of the visuals but it is assumed that these stories “merge” with the visuals and serve their meaning and, ultimately, value. They build a viewerless world:

 But when we say that the for-itself is-in-the-world, that consciousness is consciousness of the world, we must be careful to remember that the world exists confronting consciousness as an indefinite multiplicity of reciprocal relations which consciousness surveys without perspective and contemplates without a point of view. For me this glass is to the left of the decanter and a little behind it; for Pierre, it is to the right and a little in front. It is not even conceivable that a consciousness could survey the world in such a way that the glass should be simultaneously given to it at the right and at the left of the decanter, in front of it and behind it. This is by no means the consequence of a strict application of the principle of identity but because this fusion of right and left, of before and behind, would result in the total disappearance of “thises” at the heart of a primitive indistinction. Similarly if the table leg hides the designs in the rug from my sight, this is not the result of some finitude and some imperfection in my visual organs, but it is because a rug which would not be hidden by the table, a rug which would not be either under it or above it or to one side of it, would not have any relation of any kind with the table and would no longer belong to the “world” in which there is the table. The in-itself which is made manifest in the form of the this would return to its indifferent self-identity. Even space as a purely external relation would disappear. The constitution of space as a multiplicity of reciprocal relations can be effected only from the abstract point of view of science; it can not be lived, it can not even be represented. The triangle which I trace on the blackboard so as to help me in abstract reasoning is necessarily to the right of the circle tangent to one of its sides, necessarily to the extent that it is on the blackboard. And my effort is to surpass the concrete characteristics of the figure traced in chalk by not including its relation to me in my calculations any more than the thickness of the lines or the imperfection of the drawing. 
Jean-Paul Sartre
Being and Nothingness, The Body as Being-For-Itself: Facticity, 2

In the viewerless world signified by the painting, the king is not just a bi-dimensional figure on a surface. The work could very well be a sculpture without invalidating a single word of the interpretation, down to the smallest detail:

 Charles is depicted wearing the same suit of armour, riding a heavily muscled dun horse with peculiarly small head. To the right, a page proffers a helmet. Charles appears as a heroic philosopher king, contemplatively surveying his domain, carrying a baton of command, with a long sword to his side, and wearing the medallion of the Sovereign of the Order of the Garter. His melancholy, distant expression was seen as a sign of wisdom. He wears the same suit of tilt armour in both equestrian paintings […]  
English Wikipedia
Equestrian Portrait of Charles I

The interpretation quoted above captures a viewable object in a particular viewing angle (“to the right, a page proffers a helmet”) which doesn’t matter to the object: it exists from every angle, and it exists independently of whether you view it or not. The focus is on the object, not the viewing. Painting-specific narratives restore that viewing angle.

Painting-specific narratives don’t invent anything. It is known that the concept of object is not necessary to all viewing experiences. They are first a product of abstraction: the object only exists as an object insofar as I can move around it, maybe touch it, or imagine myself doing it, and empirically ascertain that a volume underlies the visuals. By the time someone has intuited the volume, they are already oblivious of the bi-dimensional representation. But the lines and shapes on the surface have their own properties, their own “story.” The fact that the representation of volume and perspective on a flat surface is just an illusion, is only one aspect of the autonomy of the surface.

Penrose triangle
How the perception of uniqueness is biased because of clichés

There is nothing trivial or objective in the assumption that all paintings must be interpreted as representing things. Picasso’s Mandolin Player might not be the obfuscated representation of a mandolin player. Even if it was, I would argue that it’s not the interesting part. What makes this assembly of geometrical patterns stand out as such, and not just be the equal of the sculpture of a mandolin player, or even the photograph of a mandolin player?

Sure, the overwhelming majority of painters actually wish for people to perceive their work as representations. But the point is not necessarily about the artist’s intention, but the potential of interpretation in general, and how people routinely put a ceiling on it—e.g., in abstract art, when the reviewer attempts, sometimes desperately, to figure out what may lurk behind the abstract:

Picasso’s Three Musicians
 Picasso paints three musicians made of flat, brightly colored, abstract shapes in a shallow, boxlike room. On the left is a clarinet player, in the middle a guitar player, and on the right a singer holding sheets of music. They are dressed as familiar figures: Pierrot, wearing a blue and white suit; Harlequinn, in an orange and yellow diamond-pattered custome; and, at right, a friar in a black robe. In front of Pierrot stands a table with a pipe and other objects, while beneath him is a dog, whose belly, legs, and tail peep out behind the musician’s legs. Like the boxy brown stage on which the three musicians perform, everything in this painting is made up of flat shapes. Behind each musician, the light brown floor is in a different place, extending much farther toward the left than the right. Framing the picture, the floor and the flat walls make the room lopsided, but the musicians seem steady. Music Makers in Harmony; It is hard to tell where one musician starts and another stops, because the shapes that create them intersect and overlap, as if they were paper cutouts. Pierrot, the figure in blue and white, holds a clarinet in his hands; one hand is connected to a long, thin, black arm, while the other hand lacks an arm. Three Musicians emphasizes lively colors, angular shapes, and flat patterns. Picasso said he was delighted when “Gertrude Stein joyfully announced… that she had at last understood what… the three musicians was meant to be. It was a still life!” Three Musicians is an example of Picasso’s Cubist style. In Cubism, the subject of the artwork is transformed into a sequence of planes, lines, and arcs. Cubism has been described as an intellectual style because the artists analyzed the shapes of their subjects and reinvented them on the canvas. The viewer must reconstruct the subject and space of the work by comparing the different shapes and forms to determine what each one represents. Through this process, the viewer participates with the artist in making the artwork make sense. 
pablopicasso.org
Review of Three Musicians

The review is figure-centric. It tries to tell “where one musician starts and another stops,” because it has somehow decided that the painting was the representation of actual musicians, with a certain idea of anatomical proportions. The analysis projects the concept of figure onto the visuals, effectively subordinating the medium to its preconceptions: the medium can only work toward what the viewer already knows. The cognitive experience is already prejudiced, even before the viewer has “reconstruct[ed] the subject and space of the work by comparing the different shapes and forms to determine what each one represents.”

In a preconception-free interpretation of the visuals, there would be no place for such a thing as confusion and “not making sense.” Only bringing up one’s preconceptions does that. “It is hard to tell where one musician starts and another stops, because the shapes that create them intersect and overlap”: it is confusing in regard to the expectation of a certain kind of figures, but confusingly enough, the exact way shapes “intersect and overlap” doesn’t suffer any confusion. And the exact way they “intersect and overlap” may precisely be the whole point. If you look at the patches of blue, they induce a kind of dislocated figure: it has a chin borrowed from the white musician, eyes borrowed from the harlequin, and it has legs, too. This figure is a painting-specific recurrence of structure. It doesn’t encumber itself with likelihood.

The classical concept of figure belongs, with other concepts such as history, location, and meaning, to an implicit culture. This culture is oblivious to painting-specific narratives, favoring instead clichés. The clichés are anticipated, to the point that non-clichés are only recognized because we are looking for the clichés. In Hans Holbein’s The Ambassadors, Slavoj Žižek calls the bizarre anamorphic skull in the center “the blot”: an inaccessible, obscure object of desire.

Hans Holbein’s The Ambassadors

The blot is most unusual, but isn’t it also unusual that in Cézanne’s The Nude Bather, an expanse of mountain in the background runs parallel to the flat ground and slopes off in a way that mirrors the shape of the puddle at the bather’s feet?

Isn’t the shape and position of the mountain in the background most unusual in relation to the other elements in Cézanne’s The Nude Bather ?

The blot in The Ambassadors is instantly recognized as such by confronting certain expectations. But in the painting-specific narrative, the fact that it doesn’t play more of a role than any similarly shaped figure would—say, a quill slanting at the same angle—reveals the interpretive bias in both the cliché and the non-cliché. As a manner of speaking, there are “blots” everywhere. Cézanne sought them in vases, fruits, and silver cutlery. Anyone can find blots looking at the racks of vegetables in a supermarket.

Flatness in Modernist painting was, in the beginning, a non-cliché that fed off the clichés. For Clement Greenberg, the “purity” of “medium specificity” is the affirmation of its independence from the figurative:

 The essence of Modernism lies, as I see it, in the use of characteristic methods of a discipline to criticize the discipline itself, not in order to subvert it but in order to entrench it more firmly in its area of competence. […]

It quickly emerged that the unique and proper area of competence of each art coincided with all that was unique in the nature of its medium. The task of self-criticism became to eliminate from the specific effects of each art any and every effect that might conceivably be borrowed from or by the medium of any other art. Thus would each art be rendered “pure,” and in its “purity” find the guarantee of its standards of quality as well as of its independence. “Purity” meant self-definition, and the enterprise of self-criticism in the arts became one of self-definition with a vengeance.

Realistic, naturalistic art had dissembled the medium, using art to conceal art; Modernism used art to call attention to art. The limitations that constitute the medium of painting—the flat surface, the shape of the support, the properties of the pigment—were treated by the Old Masters as negative factors that could be acknowledged only implicitly or indirectly. Under Modernism these same limitations came to be regarded as positive factors, and were acknowledged openly. Manet’s became the first Modernist pictures by virtue of the frankness with which they declared the flat surfaces on which they were painted. The Impressionists, in Manet’s wake, abjured underpainting and glazes, to leave the eye under no doubt as to the fact that the colors they used were made of paint that came from tubes or pots. Cézanne sacrificed verisimilitude, or correctness, in order to fit his drawing and design more explicitly to the rectangular shape of the canvas. 
Clement Greenberg
Modernist Painting

But this purity co-exists with non-Modernism, just as we saw in Picasso’s particular style of “figure”: structure, through placement and color rather than volume, fulfills the Modernist part, and the figurative quality fulfills the non-Modernist part. Greenberg himself admits as much:

 Modernist painting in its latest phase has not abandoned the representation of recognizable objects in principle. What it has abandoned in principle is the representation of the kind of space that recognizable objects can inhabit. Abstractness, or the non-figurative, has in itself still not proved to be an altogether necessary moment in the self-criticism of pictorial art, even though artists as eminent as Kandinsky and Mondrian have thought so. As such, representation, or illustration, does not attain the uniqueness of pictorial art; what does do so is the associations of things represented. All recognizable entities (including pictures themselves) exist in three-dimensional space, and the barest suggestion of a recognizable entity suffices to call up associations of that kind of space. The fragmentary silhouette of a human figure, or of a teacup, will do so, and by doing so alienate pictorial space from the literal two-dimensionality which is the guarantee of painting’s independence as an art. For, as has already been said, three-dimensionality is the province of sculpture. To achieve autonomy, painting has had above all to divest itself of everything it might share with sculpture, and it is in its effort to do this, and not so much—I repeat—to exclude the representational or literary, that painting has made itself abstract. […] And I cannot insist enough that Modernism has never meant, and does not mean now, anything like a break with the past. It may mean a devolution, an unraveling, of tradition, but it also means its further evolution. Modernist art continues the past without gap or break, and wherever it may end up it will never cease being intelligible in terms of the past. […] 
Clement Greenberg
Modernist Painting

This attachment to tradition does not prevent “purity” from serving as a “just, good, and relevant reason for appreciating masters”:

 But I want to repeat that Modernist art does not offer theoretical demonstrations. It can be said, rather, that it happens to convert theoretical possibilities into empirical ones, in doing which it tests many theories about art for their relevance to the actual practice and actual experience of art. In this respect alone can Modernism be considered subversive. Certain factors we used to think essential to the making and experiencing of art are shown not to be so by the fact that Modernist painting has been able to dispense with them and yet continue to offer the experience of art in all its essentials. The further fact that this demonstration has left most of our old value judgments intact only makes it the more conclusive. Modernism may have had something to do with the revival of the reputations of Uccello, Piero della Francesca, El Greco, Georges de la Tour, and even Vermeer; and Modernism certainly confirmed, if it did not start, the revival of Giotto's reputation; but it has not lowered thereby the standing of Leonardo, Raphael, Titian, Rubens, Rembrandt, or Watteau. What Modernism has shown is that, though the past did appreciate these masters justly, it often gave wrong or irrelevant reasons for doing so.  
Clement Greenberg
Modernist Painting

Also the Postscript, in which Greenberg defends himself from “advocating” pure art, correlates purity with the “very best art of the last hundred-odd years”:

 I want to take this chance to correct an error, one of interpretation and not of fact. Many readers, though by no means all, seem to have taken the “rationale” of Modernist art outlined here as representing a position adopted by the writer himself that is, that what he describes he also advocates. This may be a fault of the writing or the rhetoric. Nevertheless, a close reading of what he writes will find nothing at all to indicate that he subscribes to, believes in, the things that he adumbrates. (The quotation marks around pure and purity should have been enough to show that.) The writer is trying to account in part for how most of the very best art of the last hundred-odd years came about, but he’s not implying that that’s how it had to come about, much less that that’s how the best art still has to come about. “Pure” art was a useful illusion, but this doesn’t make it any the less an illusion. Nor does the possibility of its continuing usefulness make it any the less an illusion.  
Clement Greenberg
Modernist Painting, Postscript (1978)

This “usefulness” of “pure” art helped propel the “best” art over the lesser art, but there’s a caveat. The claim that the best art comes about by emphasizing “the flat surface, the shape of the support, the properties of the pigment” doesn’t actually communicate any demarcation between “best” and lesser art; Greenberg certainly came across pure paintings he found more pointless than others, unless he is to pure paintings what Marilyn Burns of Texas Chainsaw Massacre fame is to movies, according to this interview:

 TT: Do you have a favorite?

MB: They’re all favorites. I used to watch horror films on Saturday mornings. I like them all. I’m like you guys. You've got more films on your website than I know! And I thought I used to have the category down…

TT: Thank you! Which genre do you enjoy the most?

MB: I like it all. I like mysteries, suspense, horror, comedy, historical… I run the whole gamut. It’s all wonderful.

TT: Have a favorite movie?

MB: I don’t know… I can’t name favorites because I like them all.

 

Purity isn’t enough of a criterion to demarcate great art—at least it hasn’t been for a while, because it’s become a trope. As soon as both pure and non-pure paintings became equally accepted by the public, purity revealed itself to be too coarse as a criterion. In fact, non-pure paintings, even photographs, can be interpreted in terms of “the flat surface, the shape of the support, the properties of the pigment.” I could also “purify” any painting by overlaying it with solid colors, and I certainly wouldn’t expect Greenberg to hang it up there with his so-called “best art.” Likewise, non-pure art, such as photographs, can be interpreted through a purity lens. This photograph from Jay Maisel, Damsels wearing face packs posing before panels, illustrates this:

Jay Maisel, Damsels wearing face packs posing before panels

The composition divides the surface into convex regions encompassing each woman. The separation is further accentuated by the panels in the background. It’s particularly formal:

Jay maisel face packs marked.png

To be more accurate, the panels accompany the left forearm/elbow of the woman to the right. The left hand of the woman follows the convex shape (dashed red line around her head):

Jay maisel face packs marked2.png

but the left forearm/elbow “moves” it in the direction sketched by the contour of the lockers. It is a kind of “mutant” motif derived from the motif created by the face mask (cf. blue highlights). Note how the latter differs from the closed-off face mask of the other woman.

The photograph is obviously figurative. But its formality also ostentates a medium-specific narrative. It isn’t a mere matter of opposition between purity and non-purity. The described medium-specific narrative very specifically relies on connections between elements of human figures: the left hand connecting to the left forearm, the left hand connecting to the shape of the facemask through the color of the skin, and so on.

The interpretation of medium-specific narratives stresses visual patterns and doesn’t see (non)flatness. This remotely echoes the sentiment of certain authors like Deleuze and Guattari, who not only criticize the “order of the signifying and the figure,” but also its opposite, the “pure figural” as a “transgression… that remain[s] secondary nonetheless,” that is, secondary to the “schizophreny as process”:

 […] Lyotard shows in very beautiful pages that what is operating inside the dream is not the signifying, but a figural underneath, producing image configurations that use words, make them flow and traverse them following flows and positions that are not linguistic, without depending on neither the signifying nor its regulated elements. Everywhere, Lyotard destroys the order of the signifying and the figure. Rather than having the figures depend on the signifying and its effects, the signifying chain depends on the figural effects, the chain itself made up of asignifying signs, overwriting the signifying as well as the signified, treating the words like things, fabricating new units, producing, with the help of non-figurative figures, image configurations that ebb and flow […] The element of the pure figural, the “matrix-figure,” Lyotard actually calls it desire, that which leads us to the gates of schizophreny as process. But where does the reader’s impression come from, that Lyotard never ceases to stop the process, to recall the schizes to the shores that he just left, coded or overcoded territories, spaces and structures, where they only bring “transgressions,” disorders and distortions that remain secondary nonetheless, rather than form and carry away the desiring machines that oppose the structures, the intensities that oppose space? Despite his attempt at binding desire to a fundamental yes, Lyotard reintroduces lack and absence in desire, keeps it under the law of castration at the risk of bringing back the whole signifying with it, and discovers the matrix-figure in the fantasm, the mere fantasm that obscures the desiring production, all desire as effective production. 
 […] dans le rêve, Lyotard montre dans de très belles pages que ce qui travaille n’est pas le signifiant, mais un figural en dessous, faisant surgir des configurations d’images qui se servent des mots, les font couler et les coupent suivant des flux et des points qui ne sont pas linguistiques, en ne dépendent pas du signifiant ni de ses éléments réglés. Partout donc Lyotard renverse l’ordre du signifiant et de la figure. Ce ne sont pas les figures qui dépendent du signifiant et de ses effets, c’est la chaîne signifiante qui dépend des effets figuraux, faite elle-même de signes asignifiants, écrasant les signifiants comme les signifiés, traîtant les mots comme des choses, fabriquant de nouvelles unités, faisant avec des figures non figuratives des configurations d’images qui se font et se défont. […] L’élément du figural pur, la “figure-matrice,” Lyotard la nomme bien désir, qui nous conduit aux portes de la schizophrénie comme processus. Mais d’où vient pourtant l’impression du lecteur que Lyotard n’a de cesse d’arrêter le processus, et de rabattre les schizes sur les rivages qu’il vient de quitter, territoires codés ou surcodés, espaces et structures, 'où ils ne font plus qu’apporter des “trangressions,” des troubles et des déformations malgré tout secondaires, au lieu de former et d’emporter plus loin les machines désirantes qui s’opposent aux structures, les intensités qui s’opposent aux espaces ? C’est que, malgré sa tentative de lier le désir à un oui fondamental, Lyotard réintroduit le manque et l’absence dans le désir, le maintient sous la loi de castration au risque de ramener avec elle tout le signifiant, et découvre la matrice de la figure dans le fantasme, le simple fantasme qui vient occulter la production désirante, tout le désir comme production effective. 
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari
Savages, barbarians and civilized men, in Anti-Œdipus

The interpretation of the medium-specific narrative doesn’t rely on a general theory of art, nor on a theory of the medium such as “medium purity.” It doesn’t rely on a theory of the “very best art of the last hundred-odd years,” either. Any consensus on “the best art” is based on clichés, and the interpretation of the medium-specific narrative doesn’t look for clichés.

Rediscovering graphical narration. Real-time sand art as an eye-opener. Graphical narration in movies. A comics-specific narrative from Goossens’ Touti and his exhaust pipe.

When it comes to single images, it seems weird to speak of a narrative. But this weirdness is a result of an amnesic way of looking at images. For if one would only be so inclined as to take the placement of a house, the branch of a tree, or the directionality of the texture of a loaf of bread, to be as relevant to the image as death is to a crime novel, one would immediately see the potential of a “graphical story” with multiple heretofore ignored “graphical events.” The events are the visual sensations as our gaze moves across the canvas. Each color transition, each intersection, each pattern can be recorded into a medium-specific narrative, just like storyline events are recorded into the timeline of a regular novel.

These graphical events can be insisted upon through cinematic means: image sequences (polyptichs, comic strips) or animations. In this performace on Britain’s Got Talent: The Champions, Kseniya Simonova uses real-time sand art to tell a 3-minute graphical story. Here, a bird flock progressively morphs into the facial features of a school girl:

Sandart0.jpg
Sandart1.jpg

The sky darkens. Lightning strikes, then it becomes IV lines as the girl gets transposed into a hospital room:

Sandart2.jpg
Sandart3.jpg

This kind of graphics-specific narration is a rarity in movies, even though movies can technically do everything sand art does. Their main focus is on traditional narratives, which is reflected by the fact that many movies are adaptations of written stories. On the other hand, sand art is rather light on story. In our example, the story is actually so cheesy (a child gets hospitalized then recovers, and it all ends with the line “Never give up”) that it would make an embarassing movie without the graphics-specific narrative. It should be noted that the medium specificity emphasized here is graphical and ignores the technicality of performing with sand. By comparison, another cinematic form, shadow play dancing (e.g., the band Silhouettes which performed on America’s Got Talent), tends to depict stories that are as cheesy but without the graphics-specific narration, as its focus is more on the technicality of creating mundane shapes with human shadows.

Movies with distinctive medium-specific narratives do exist though, such as The Vanishing (1988), itself a book adaptation. In that film, a car is inside a tunnel. Inside, a woman, called Saskia, tells her man, Rex Hoffman:

“My nightmare. I had it again last night.”

Hoffman remembers:

“That you’re inside a golden egg, and you can’t get out, and you float all alone through space forever.”

The car runs out of gas inside the tunnel. After a brief argument, Hoffman leaves a panicking Saskia in the car to seek help. When he comes back with a can, she’s not in the car anymore. He drives the car out of the tunnel, and as he emerges, he sees her framed by the bright opening of the tunnel, almost like a golden egg:

Thevanishing1.jpg

At the next rest area, Saskia disappears, probably abducted. Years later, Hoffman still obsesses over her disappearance and does everything in his power to learn what happened to her. On television, he recounts:

“She dreamed that we’d meet somewhere in space, each of us imprisoned inside a golden egg. In my dream, we also found each other, out there in space. And I’ve interpreted this dream as a sign.”

When he finally meets the abductor, he says:

“I don’t want to punish you. I don’t care about you. All I want to know is what happened to her.”

The abductor agrees to let him know but only under the condition that he lets himself get put into sleep. He accepts after an intense inner debate. He wakes up in the dark and bangs his head while trying to get up. Using a lighter he finds out that he’s stuck inside a coffin. The lighter’s flame fades into the memory of the tunnel opening with Saskia inside:

Thevanishing2.jpg

The last shot of the movie is of a newspaper showing the portraits of Saskia and Hoffman side by side.

Thevanishing3.jpg

Then, a black mask is superimposed over the newspaper, enclosing the portraits inside egg shapes:

Thevanishing4.jpg

A medium-specific narrative therefore leads to fulfilling the golden egg prophecy in a very visual interpretation, from the lighting of the inside of the coffin to the newspaper portraits. Interestingly, the 1993 Hollywood remake, by the same director, takes away the medium-specific narration in favor of action movie tropes.

Daniel Goossens’ comic Touti and his exhaust pipe nicely illustrates the difference between graphical and event-based story-telling. Comics feature two pedagogical advantages over traditional painting: their narrative format, and text. Captions can narrate events, so they can force a break-the-fourth-wall point-of-view onto the reader, leading them to rethink their relationship to the visual medium, often with a comical effect not unlike René Magritte’s This is not a pipe.

René Magritte’s This is not a pipe

Here’s a page from Goossens’ comics:

Page 2 of Goossens’s Touti and his exhaust pipe

The policeman seems to signal Touti to pull over because of a malfunctioning exhaust pipe, but he corrects the narrator: “No, it’s not for that. It’s to interrupt the monotony. Here, in the flat lands, the horizon [cf. blue highlight] is monotonous, and it is fitting that a policeman cuts through it using his silhouette [cf. red highlight].”

His speech (comically) emphasizes his verticality rather than the concept of “officer of the Law.” The story then builds up toward a car crash:

Page 3 of Goossens’s Touti and his exhaust pipe

Remarkably enough, the car runs into a tree [red highlight] “cutting through the horizon [blue highlight]” just like the vertical officer. A comics-specific narrative thus emerges.

The story changes altogether when one switches to a more traditional interpretation. The policeman’s appearance becomes a casual event in the timeline. When all is said and done, all he did was advise Touti to have his exhaust pipe changed. By ending on a car crash, the story expresses the “irony of fate:” at the time of the crash, the car had just been repaired, and to add insult to injury, the tragic turn of events came about due to the advice of the policeman. This interpretation is independent from the graphical representation. For example, seeing the crash from above, instead of having the tree “cut through the horizon,” wouldn’t change the interpretation. There would be a graphically different, but story-wise identical, collision, and a different medium-specific narrative (without the graphical reference to the officer).

Rediscovering intra-textuality

Staying inside the text medium: the New Criticism movement. The cliché/non-cliché bias.

Traditionally, interpretation treats prose differently from poetry, poetry differently from sound poetry, etc. We naturally expect interpretations of poems to be more medium-specific than interpretations of novels, if only because they will be more attentive to text-specific things like phrasal structure, rhyming, and so on:

 New Criticism developed as a reaction to the older philological and literary history schools, which, influenced by nineteenth-century German scholarship, focused on the history and meaning of individual words and their relation to foreign and ancient languages, comparative sources, and the biographical circumstances of the authors. These approaches, it was felt, tended to distract from the text and meaning of a poem and entirely neglect its aesthetic qualities in favor of teaching about external factors. On the other hand, the literary appreciation school, which limited itself to pointing out the “beauties” and morally elevating qualities of the text, was disparaged by the New Critics as too subjective and emotional. Condemning this as a version of Romanticism, they aimed for newer, systematic and objective method.  
English Wikipedia
History, in New Criticism

Just as the blot can coerce interpretation in plastic arts, literary content can force the interpreter’s hand. Sound poetry, for example, imposes its own codes:

 Some consider Mallarmé one of the French poets most difficult to translate into English. The difficulty is due in part to the complex, multilayered nature of much of his work, but also to the important role that the sound of the words, rather than their meaning, plays in his poetry. When recited in French, his poems allow alternative meanings which are not evident on reading the work on the page. For example, Mallarmé’s Sonnet en “-yx” opens with the phrase ses purs ongles (“her pure nails”), whose first syllables when spoken aloud sound very similar to the words c’est pur son (“it’s pure sound”). Indeed, the “pure sound” aspect of his poetry has been the subject of musical analysis and has inspired musical compositions. These phonetic ambiguities are very difficult to reproduce in a translation which must be faithful to the meaning of the words.  
English Wikipedia
Stéphane Mallarmé

But there’s an interpretive bias as soon as one ignores sound in places we don’t expect it to matter. Such is the case for the final lines of Ode on a Grecian Urn, whose rhyme structure—“Beauty is truth, truth beauty, that is all/Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know”—wasn’t really interpreted by the majority of academics (and at best confused them) who chose instead to debate about the meaning and who truly spoke to whom: poet to reader, urn to reader, poet to urn, poet to figures on the urn?

The question of scale: the medium-specific micro-narratives

Medium-specific narratives in literature are nothing new. For example, reasoning fallacies offer various forms of medium-specific narratives. What they lack in reality, scientific reliability, and practical applicability, they gain by being amusing, entertaining, witty, comical, interesting, artful, and limitless. Syllogistic fallacies could very well be described as “patterns of resolved stresses,” as the New Criticism describes poetry. “Stress” accrues with each additional premise, and the conclusion resolves the “stress” mostly by “sounding natural:”

  1. All inhabitants of other planets drink water.
  2. All Martians are inhabitants of another planet.
  3. Therefore, some Martians drink water.

The symmetric quality of the transition from “All inhabitants of other planets drink water” to “Therefore, some Martians drink water,” in both sentence structure and word usage, plays no small part in the efficiency of the argumentation. Rewriting the conclusion into a less symmetric form would go a long way toward exposing the fallacy:

  1. All inhabitants of other planets drink water.
  2. All Martians are inhabitants of another planet.
  3. Therefore, among all the beings who drink water, there must exist at least one Martian.

Consider another example:

  1. All students have been young.
  2. My grandfather has been young.
  3. Therefore, my grandfather is a student.

The fallacy relies on symmetry, both semantically and structurally. Should the premises be very distinct from each other, this wouldn’t even be considered a good fallacy. The following rewrite would be far less convincing:

  1. All political leaders, doctors, and students have been young.
  2. My grandfather has been young.
  3. So he is a student.

In comparison, a rational conclusion is tediously obvious, down-to-earth, tautological, uncomical.

  1. All political leaders, doctors, and students have been young.
  2. My grandfather has been young.
  3. He may have been a political leader, a doctor, and/or a student, but it is not necessary.

Fallacies are not just syllogisms that fit into 3 sentences. They routinely occur informally, most unassumingly in scientific literature. The reader doesn’t always need a science degree in order to detect them, because a fallacy, as a medium-specific narrative, can be expressed in the text itself, in a self-contained way.

Not all of science is equally vulnerable to fallacy. Compared to axiomatic science, empirical science as a collection of universal laws (e.g., “the action is always equal to the reaction”) is more “entertaining,” whether because of the leaps of faith that, as Hume pointed out, are required to elevate experimental observations to universal statements, or because of the wishful thinking underneath their justification, especially in the fields of applied science. For example, in The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Popper refutes the argument that his concept of “degree of corroboration of probability hypotheses” is reducible to traditional probability:

 Consider the next throw with a homogeneous die. Let x be the statement ‘six will turn up’; let y be its negation, that is to say, let y = ~x; and let z be the information ‘an even number will turn up’. We have the following absolute probabilities:

p(x) = 1/6; p(y) = 5/6; p(z) = 1/2.

Moreover, we have the following relative probabilities:

p(x, z) = 1/3; p(y, z) = 2/3.

We see that x is supported by the information z, for z raises the probability of x from 1/6 to 2/6 = 1/3. We also see that y is undermined by z, for z lowers the probability of y by the same amount from 5/6 to 4/6 = 2/3. Nevertheless, we have p(x, z) < p(y, z). This example proves the following theorem:

(5) There exist statements, x, y, and z, which satisfy the formula,

p(x, z) > p(x) & p(y, z) < p(y) & p(x, z) < p(y, z).

Obviously, we may replace here ‘p(y, z) < p(y)’ by the weaker ‘p(y, z) ≤ p(y)’.

This theorem is, of course, far from being paradoxical. And the same holds for its corollary (6) which we obtain by substituting for ‘p(x, z) > p(x)’ and ‘p(y, z) ≤ p(y)’ the expressions ‘Co(x, z)’ and ‘¬Co(y, z)’—that is to say ‘non-Co(y, z)’—respectively, in accordance with formula (1) above:

(6) There exist statements x, y and z which satisfy the formula

Co(x, z) & ¬Co(y, z) & p(x, z) < p(y, z).

Like (5), theorem (6) expresses a fact we have established by our example: that x may be supported by z, and y undermined by z, and that nevertheless x, given z, may be less probable than y, given z. There at once arises, however, a clear self-contradiction if we now identify in (6) degree of confirmation C(a, b) and probability p(a, b). In other words, the formula

(**) Co(x, z) & ¬Co(y, z) & C(x, z) < C(y, z)

(that is, ‘z confirms x but not y, yet z also confirms x to a lesser degree than y’) is clearly self-contradictory.

Thus we have proved that the identification of degree of corroboration or confirmation with probability (and even with likelihood) is absurd on both formal and intuitive grounds: it leads to self-contradiction. 
Karl Popper
Appendix *ix. Corroboration, the Weight of Evidence, and Statistical Tests, in The Logic of Scientific Discovery

However, formula (**) is not necessarily self-contradictory, both on intuitive and mathematical grounds. Let’s see why.

Popper provides a metaphor for formula (**): “x has the property P (for example, the property ‘warm’) and y has not the property P and y has the property P in a higher degree than x (for example, y is warmer than x).” Put like this, (**) certainly seems self-contradictory.

But Popper is misleading when he equates C(x, z) < C(y, z) to “y has the property P in a higher degree than x,” because by definition, this would mean we have “p(y, z) > p(y) to a higher degree than p(x, z) > p(x).” We are comparing 2 statements (“p(y, z) > p(y)” on one hand, and “p(x, z) > p(x)” on the other) each with a different right-hand side, namely p(x) and p(y). I can say that Alice is taller than Bob in a higher degree than Cedric is taller than David, but it’s not contradictory to say that Cedric is taller than Alice.

So a more accurate metaphor for P would be “warmer” rather than just “warm,” with an important emphasis on warmer than something. Obviously, if x gets warmer (Co(x, z)) and y cooler (¬Co(y, z)), y can still be warmer than x because it was very hot to start with, so having C(x, z) < C(y, z) (“y is warmer than something, to a higher degree than x is warmer than something”) doesn’t seem contradictory anymore.

Such losses in metaphor share with syllogisms the same propensity for erasing structural relationships through “honest mistakes” such as the shortcut from “warmer” to “warm.” They underly an infinite number of unique narratives that occur when translating back and forth between informal and formal language. Popper himself debunks Heisenberg’s use of informal language in what belongs to the long list of sensationalist interpretations of numbers and formulas that theoretical physics is especially fond of (e.g., the many-worlds interpretation, Schrödinger’s cat, time dilation):

 [The problem following here has since become famous under the name ‘The problem of the (discontinuous) reduction of the wave packet’. Some leading physicists told me in 1934 that they agreed with my trivial solution, yet the problem still plays a most bewildering role in the discussion of the quantum theory, after more than twenty years.]

Imagine a semi-translucent mirror, i.e. a mirror which reflects part of the light, and lets part of it through. The formally singular probability that one given photon (or light quantum) passes through the mirror, [math]\displaystyle{ (_αP_k(β)) }[/math], may be taken to be equal to the probability that it will be reflected; we therefore have

[math]\displaystyle{ (_αP_k(β) = _αP_k(\bar{β}) = {1 \over 2}) }[/math]

This probability estimate, as we know, is defined by objective statistical probabilities; that is to say, it is equivalent to the hypothesis that one half of a given class α of light quanta will pass through the mirror whilst the other half will be reflected. Now let a photon k fall upon the mirror; and let it next be experimentally ascertained that this photon has been reflected: then the probabilities seem to change suddenly, as it were, and discontinuously. It is as though before the experiment they had both been equal to [math]\displaystyle{ ({1 \over 2}) }[/math], while after the fact of the reflection became known, they had suddenly turned into 0 and to 1, respectively. It is plain that this example is really the same as that given in section 71. [That is to say, the probabilities ‘change’ only in so far as α is replaced by β. Thus [math]\displaystyle{ (_αP(β)) }[/math] remains unchanged [math]\displaystyle{ ({1 \over 2}) }[/math]; but [math]\displaystyle{ (_\bar{β}P(β)) }[/math], of course, equals 0, just as [math]\displaystyle{ (_βP(β)) }[/math] equals 1.] And it hardly helps to clarify the situation if this experiment is described, as by Heisenberg, in such terms as the following: ‘By the experiment [i.e. the measurement by which we find the reflected photon], a kind of physical action (a reduction of wave packets) is exerted from the place where the reflected half of the wave packet is found upon another place—as distant as we choose—where the other half of the packet just happens to be’; a description to which he adds: ‘this physical action is one which spreads with super-luminal velocity.’ This is unhelpful since our original probabilities, [math]\displaystyle{ (_αP_k(β)) }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ (_αP_k(\bar{β})) }[/math], remain equal to [math]\displaystyle{ ({1 \over 2}) }[/math]. All that has happened is the choice of a new reference class—β or [math]\displaystyle{ (\bar{β}) }[/math], instead of α—a choice strongly suggested to us by the result of the experiment, i.e. by the information [math]\displaystyle{ (k \in β) }[/math] or [math]\displaystyle{ (k \in \bar{β}) }[/math], respectively. Saying of the logical consequences of this choice (or, perhaps, of the logical consequences of this information) that they ‘spread with super-luminal velocity’ is about as helpful as saying that twice two turns with super-luminal velocity into four. A further remark of Heisenberg’s, to the effect that this kind of propagation of a physical action cannot be used to transmit signals, though true, hardly improves matters. 
Karl Popper
The Logic of Scientific Discovery

Many fallacies share the liberal use of language, but their form and scale can vary from syllogisms to very elaborate theses.

Non-fiction literature
Prerequisite to rediscovery: stoicism in the face of contradictions, errors and dislikes. Being open-minded and not limited by taste.

One has absolute freedom to overlook the medium-specific narratives. So does the author of fallacies. They can freely overlook their “shortcomings”—I put that in quotes, because fallacies may be inconsequential, or even work out for the best. Most would agree that contradictions in a scientific theory should be cause enough to ditch it. Yet, a self-contradictory theory has no shame. It will outlive its intolerant readers. It weaves a tissue of contradictions, contradictions that break conventions, “don’t make sense,” or are so full of involuntary errors that even the author repudiated it. Just like science fiction, it doesn’t care.

When we ditch a logic system because it is self-contradictory, we do so for the same reason we ditch any other self-contradictory logic system: a single contradiction puts the whole system in jeopardy, since any proposition and its contrary can be logically derived from it. So, for example, if you prove 1 = 2, you can also prove 3 = 800. Yet the text that describes a self-contradictory logic system only mentions a very small subset of the infinite set of possible texts, and it does so in its own way. The confusion in Popper, as quoted in the previous section, is not only between the comparative and absolute forms, i.e., between “warm” and “warmer,” between “confirmed” and “confirmed to a higher degree.” There is a very medium-specific narrative that makes the confusion very peculiar. Popper makes the formula “Co(x, z) & ¬Co(y, z) & p(x, z) < p(y, z)” appear all the more self-contradictory because he first defined p(x, z) > p(x) as the absolute form Co(x, z) (“z confirms x”) which resembles C(x, z). This is a case where the fallacy highly depends on the presentation using a mix of formal and natural discourse: introduce an abbrevation Co(x, z) that makes it easy to define in an informal and amnesic way (“z confirms x” which forgets the precise form of the inequality p(x, z) > p(x)), then inject that informal definition in the formula C(x, z) < C(y, z) to obtain the contradictory-looking informal statement “z confirms x to a lesser degree than z confirms y”: there you have a medium-specific narrative.

The contradictions kind of “stop” the text. Not that one is forced to stop reading. The usual way people reconcile contradictions with the undisturbed flow of the text is by conceiving them as a mosaic of good and bad points. In other words, we fill the “holes” of the fallacies with the holes that make up the mosaic.

 In general, we are too quick to discover contradictions in reading phenomena, for the sake of either declaring them irreducible, or resolving them by demonstrating that they are only apparent, depending on the tastes. In truth, there is never any contradiction, apparent or real, but only degrees of humor. And, since reading itself has its own degrees of humor, from black to white, with which it values the coexisting degrees of what is read, the only problem is always that of the distribution on a scale of intensities which assigns the location and usage of every thing, every being or scene: there is this and then that, and let’s make do with it, too bad if we don’t like it.  
 D’une manière générale, on a trop vite fait dans les phénomènes de lecture de découvrir des contradictions, soit pour les déclarer irréductibles, soit pour les résoudre ou montrer qu’elles sont seulement apparentes, suivant les goûts. En vérité, il n’y a jamais de contradictions, apparentes ou réelles, mais seulement des degrés d’humour. Et, comme la lecture a elle-même ses degrés d’humour, du noir au blanc, avec lesquels elle évalue les degrés coexistants de ce qu’elle lit, le seul problème est toujours celui d’une répartition sur une échelle d’intensités qui assigne la place et l’usage de chaque chose, chaque être ou chaque scène : il y a ceci et puis cela, et débrouillons-nous avec, tant pis si ça ne nous plaît pas.  
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari
Psychanalyse et familialisme, in Anti-Œdipus

The stopping does not only apply to contradictions, but also to a whole repertoire of attention-grabbers: writing style, subject matter… anything, really, that can be valued. In music, we may stop listening to a death metal song after just a few notes just because the Cookie Monster vocals put us off. We may not finish a book because we disagree with its main points, or find it hard to care about the characters, or are just getting bored by the first pages. But even a boring start may lead to a rewarding overall experience. This applies to other media as well. In visual art, contradictions take the form of confusion, e.g., confusion between the mundane and the sublime, the lively and the still, the planar and the perspective, the colorful and the monochromatic, the imitative and the non-imitative, etc. In a movie, we may take issue with something bad, distasteful, repulsive. Yet the movie continues to live its life. We are the Jean-François Lyotard that Deleuze and Guattari criticized for “never ceasing to stop the process, to recall the schizes to the shores that he just left, coded or overcoded territories, spaces and structures, where they only bring ‘transgressions,’ disorders and distortions that remain secondary nonetheless.”

 Learning to see—accustoming the eye to calmness, to patience, to letting things come up to it; postponing judgment, learning to go around and grasp each individual case from all sides. That is the first preliminary schooling for spirituality: not to react at once to a stimulus, but to gain control of all the inhibiting, excluding instincts. Learning to see, as I understand it, is almost what, unphilosophically speaking, is called a strong will: the essential feature is precisely not to “will”—to be able to suspend decision. All unspirituality, all vulgar commonness, depend on the inability to resist a stimulus: one must react, one follows every impulse. In many cases, such a compulsion is already pathology, decline, a symptom of exhaustion—almost everything that unphilosophical crudity designates with the word “vice” is merely this physiological inability not to react. A practical application of having learned to see: as a learner, one will have become altogether slow, mistrustful, recalcitrant. One will let strange, new things of every kind come up to oneself, inspecting them with hostile calm and withdrawing one’s hand. To have all doors standing open, to lie servilely on one’s stomach before every little fact, always to be prepared for the leap of putting oneself into the place of, or of plunging into, others and other things—in short, the famous modern “objectivity”—is bad taste, is ignoble par excellence.  
Friedrich Nietzsche
WHAT THE GERMANS LACK, in Twilight of the Idols

This discourse seems to echo the good old plea for open-mindedness. However, when people beg for open-mindedness, it is usually either in the hope of changing other people’s minds or with the mindset that others should have better tastes. In effect, the others are being criticized for their tastes, albeit in a politically correct way. “Be open-minded, what you don’t like is actually very good, you’ll see.” On the contrary, I absolutely don’t intend to change people’s minds about what they don’t like. What people didn’t like, they’ll still dislike, whatever it is they don’t like. I only speak from the perspective of the medium-specific narrative, which might very well be different from “what they don’t like,” although both are materially the same content. To use a metaphor: feces are distasteful and repulsive, a useless by-product (who would complain if we never had to defecate ever again?), yet this doesn’t take anything away from the elegance of a rural environment where one can defecate in the open and let Nature make it disappear in a matter of minutes, especially when compared to our artificial sewage systems.

 Dung beetles play a remarkable role in agriculture. By burying and consuming dung, they improve nutrient recycling and soil structure. They also protect livestock, such as cattle, by removing the dung which, if left, could provide habitat for pests such as flies. Therefore, many countries have introduced the creatures for the benefit of animal husbandry. In developing countries, the beetles are especially important as an adjunct for improving standards of hygiene. The American Institute of Biological Sciences reports that dung beetles save the United States cattle industry an estimated US$380 million annually through burying above-ground livestock feces.  
English Wikipedia
Dung Beetle
Stoicism in the conventionalist interpretation of scientific literature.

The conventionalist interpretation of an axiomatic system consists in viewing the fundamental concepts as “implicit definitions:”

 The view of classical rationalism that the ‘axioms’ of certain systems, e.g., those of Euclidean geometry, must be regarded as immediately or intuitively certain, or self-evident, will not be discussed here. I will only mention that I do not share this view. I consider two different interpretations of any system of axioms to be admissible. The axioms may be regarded either (i) as conventions, or they may be regarded (ii) as empirical or scientific hypotheses. (i) If the axioms are regarded as conventions then they tie down the use or meaning of the fundamental ideas (or primitive terms, or concepts) which the axioms introduce; they determine what can and what cannot be said about these fundamental ideas. Sometimes the axioms are described as ‘implicit definitions’ of the ideas which they introduce. This view can perhaps be elucidated by means of an analogy between an axiomatic system and a (consistent and soluble) system of equations. 
Karl Popper
Some possibilities of interpreting a system of axioms, in The Logic of Scientific Discovery

As Popper stresses, the conventionalist view, although unacceptable for some purposes, is unattackable: isn’t the conventionalist at liberty to consider a definition as he pleases? In fact, this view is unacceptable in Popper’s sense precisely because it makes any theoretical system unattackable. If a theory in geometry contains an axiom that states that a point has a surface, the conventionalist view does not claim that it is an actual observation or anything measurable. It is some definition of the point—or more accurately, the word “point.” Definition is only the arbitrary foundation to an arbitrary system. The focus is not the definition itself, but what one makes of it: something that can be aesthetical, witty, comical, or even useful. What if one invents a geometry where Euclid’s parallel postulate does not hold: “If a straight line falling on two straight lines make the interior angles on the same side less than two right angles, the two straight lines, if produced indefinitely, meet on that side on which are the angles less than the two right angles.” One could construe this as step toward elliptic/hyperbolic geometries and curved space, where basic theorems like the Pythagorean theorem or the triangle postulate—“The sum of the angles in every triangle is 180°”—do not hold anymore. This, in turn, helps to formulate the transition from special to general relativity in modern physics:

 The term [of special relativity] is currently used more generally to refer to any case in which gravitation is not significant. General relativity is the generalization of special relativity to include gravitation. In general relativity, gravity is described using non-Euclidean geometry, so that gravitational effects are represented by curvature of spacetime; special relativity is restricted to flat spacetime.  
English Wikipedia
Special relativity

For some, this would be cause enough for ditching modern physics. Non-Euclidean geometry is neither intuitive, nor observable, nor simple—for what would be a space where “parallel” lines intersect? However, the non-intuitive theories may lead to the prediction of observable effects. And non-intuitive concepts can simplify theory:

 Based on Henri Poincaré’s conventionalism, philosophers such as Pierre Duhem (1914) or Hugo Dingler (1920) argued that the classical concepts of space, time, and geometry were, and will always be, the most convenient expressions in natural science, therefore the concepts of relativity cannot be correct. This was criticized by proponents of logical positivism such as Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, or Reichenbach. They argued that Poincaré’s conventionalism could be modified, as to bring it into accord with relativity. Although it’s true, that the basis assumptions of Newtonian mechanics are more simple, it can only be brought into accord with modern experiments by inventing auxiliary hypotheses. On the other hand, relativity doesn’t need such hypotheses, thus from a conceptual viewpoint, relativity is in fact more simple than Newtonian mechanics.  
English Wikipedia
Criticism of relativity theory

But this implies that one first accepts the definitions as they are, rather than harping on them and potentially missing the point, such as the ability to make predictions or construct an elegant theory with practical applications.

Rediscovering philosophy

Even if it’s not considered art, a philosophical work (or any written work in general) has text-specific narratives. In a field where most problems originate from the definitions, the interpretation of a text-specific narrative has the tastefulness not to descend into the spiral of surmising with different definitions to prove one’s point. Instead, it reveals the uniqueness of a thought process.

A point can be made that without its false problems , philosophy would be boring. Its arguments would either be perfectly logical to the point of tautology, or verge on the mystic. For example, the talk about objectivity and reality would dumb down to the assertion that “objects” are external to me in the sense of their spatial relationship to my body. Granted, it wouldn’t be as interesting as speculating of an external reality “in-itself,” lying outside my perception. This is the classic case of a philosopher who creates “interesting” false problems that keep the next generations of philosophers busy for nothing. Ironically, these critics, being philosophers themselves, can’t help but make what is bred in the bone come out in the flesh. So there are some cases where the critic is spot-on, but in their own philosophy walks into pretty much the same traps as their peers—cf. Schopenhauer tackling Leibniz or Hegel.

Definition issues are often supported by selective amnesia. For example, the author presupposes A to prove some statement (in favor of the author’s thesis), then presupposes the antithesis of A (amnesia of the thesis of A) to prove another statement. Amnesia can happen at all scopes. At the phrase and paragraph level, amnesia can take the form of a traditional figure of speech. As the scope gets broader, amnesia takes more unique forms less acknowledged by academic literary analysis.

At the phrase level, take the infamous “DLC fiasco,” where a game editor, Capcom, delivers a game disc on the Playstation with locked content that can be unlocked for a fee. Then came the voices of protest:

 I’m talking about fair trade and they don’t have the right to revoke anything you have purchased by playing the “you just paid for a license” card.  
Someone on some gamer forum

But if “you just paid for a license,” then Capcom doesn’t revoke anything you paid for by locking away the content, since the lock is part of the license, which is where amnesia struck. Of course, this doesn’t mean people don’t have the right to be discontent, but they can’t expect to be any more legit than someone protesting that a car should come with all the accessories because the manufacturer has the keys to the warehouse.

At the paragraph level, in Anti-Œdipus Deleuze and Guattari take a bite at Freud’s Œdipus complex. In particular, they argue that incest is impossible in the system in which it exists:

 […] the names, the appellations no longer designate intensive states, but discernible persons. Discernibility settles on the sister and the mother as prohibited spouses. The reason is that persons, with the names that now designate them, do not exist prior to the prohibitions as spouses. Robert Jaulin says it well: “The mythical discourse has as its theme the passage from the indifference to incest to its prohibition. Implicit or explicit, this theme underlies all the myths; it is therefore a formal property of this language.” We must conclude that, strictly speaking, incest does not and cannot exist. We are always on this side of incest, in a series of intensities that is ignorant of discernible persons; or else beyond incest, in an extension that recognizes them, that constitutes them, but that does not constitute them without making them impossible as sexual partners. One can commit incest only after a series of substitutions that always moves us away from it, that is to say, with a person who is equivalent to the mother or the sister only by virtue of being neither: she who is discernible as a possible spouse.  
 […] les noms, les appellations ne désignent plus des états intensifs, mais des personnes discernables. La discernabilité se pose sur la sœur, la mère comme épouses interdites. C’est que les personnes, avec les noms qui les désignent maintenant, ne préexistent pas aux interdits qui les constituent comme telles. Mère et sœur ne préexistent pas à leur interdiction comme épouses. Robert Jaulin le dit très bien: “Le discours mythique a pour thème le passage de l’indifférence à l’inceste à sa prohibition : implicite ou explicite, ce thème est sous-jacent à tous les mythes; il est donc une propriété formelle de ce langage.” De l’inceste, il faut conclure à la lettre qu’il n’existe pas, ne peut pas exister. L’inceste, on est toujours en deçà, dans une série d’intensités qui ignore les personnes discernables; ou bien au-delà, dans une extension qui les reconnaît, qui les constitue, mais qui ne les constitue pas sans les rendre impossibles comme partenaires sexuels. L’inceste, on ne peut le faire qu’à la suite d’une série de substitutions qui nous en éloigne toujours, c’est-à-dire avec une personne qui ne vaut pour la mère ou la sœur qu’à force de ne pas l’être: celle qui est discernable comme épouse possible.  
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari

In the quoted paragraph, “prohibited spouse” was replaced by “impossible spouse,” so that, indeed, it is now impossible to commit incest, since, by definition, incest now identifies mother and sister as impossible spouses—i.e., having sex with a woman makes her non-mother and non-sister, by definition.

In The Capital, Karl Marx demonstrates the laborer’s contribution to increased production:

 In agriculture the land under cultivation cannot be increased without the advance of more seed and manure. But this advance once made, the purely mechanical working of the soil itself produces a marvellous effect on the amount of the product. A greater quantity of labour, done by the same number of labourers as before, thus increases the fertility, without requiring any new advance in the instruments of labour. It is once again the direct action of man on Nature which becomes an immediate source of greater accumulation, without the intervention of any new capital.  
Karl Marx
Circumstances that, Independently of the Proportional Division of Surplus-Value into Capital and Revenue, Determine the Amount of Accumulation, in Capital Volume One

Here the “advance of [more seed and manure] is made,” but in the concluding phrase of the paragraph, the increased production now occurs “without the intervention of any new capital.” This rhetorical trick allows Marx to make the labourers steal the show.

Gottlob Frege’s the Foundations of Arithmetic offers a good example of book-level amnesia. It enters a particular category, that of not keeping a promise made at the beginning of a book. The book starts with this:

 When we ask someone what the number one is, or what the symbol 1 means, we get as a rule the answer “Why, a thing.” And if we go on to point out that the proposition “the number one is a thing” is not a definition, because it has the definite article on one side and the indefinite on the other, or that it only assigns the number one to the class of things, without stating which thing it is, then we shall very likely be invited to select something for ourselves—anything we please—to call one. […] If a concept fundamental to a mighty science gives rise to difficulties, then it is surely an imperative task to investigate it more closely until those difficulties are overcome; especially as we shall hardly succeed in finally clearing up negative numbers, or fractional or complex numbers, so long as our insight into the foundation of the whole structure of arithmetic is still defective.  
Gottlob Frege
The Foundations of Arithmetic

Now, let’s teleport to the end of the book and examine Frege’s own definition of the “number”:

 The Number which belongs to the concept F is the extension of the concept “concept equal to the concept F”, wherein a concept F is called equal to a concept G if there exists the possibility of one-one correlation referred to above. In this definition the sense of the expression “extension of a concept” is assumed to be known. This way of getting over the difficulty cannot be expected to meet with universal approval, and many will prefer other methods of removing the doubt in question. I attach no decisive importance even to bringing in the extensions of concepts at all.  
Gottlob Frege
The Foundations of Arithmetic

Therefore Frege’s Number relies on an “indefinite” (the “extension of concept”), and thus ends up doing what he warned not to do (not “stating which thing it is”).

Rediscovering repetition

Repetition is a significant tool of artistic expression. For example, the trope of the story loop, where the ending reflects the beginning, is quite common, from literature (e.g., Lewis Carrol’s Alice In Wonderland) to video games (e.g., The Last of Us, where the main protagonist carries to safety a girl the same way he carried his late daughter at the start of the game). In poetry, repetition of sound and structure has been thoroughly studied. Repetition is also a well-known comedic device—e.g., Monty Python’s Déjà Vu sketch.

 The polypoids were burning in the wood

A stone caught fire The castle caught fire The forest caught fire The men caught fire The women caught fire The birds caught fire The fish caught fire The water caught fire The sky caught fire The ashes caught fire The smoke caught fire The fire caught fire Everything caught fire Caught fire, caught fire.

 
Eugène Ionesco
The Bald Soprano

As a result, the concept of repetition is commonly known as a trope. So although it is fundamentally a temporal concept, it seems to compress and abstract time. Same with the concept of tempo. In classical music, one is used to designate the sections of a concerto or symphony by a blanket tempo. A Vivaldi concerto, for example, is often divided into 3 movements identified by the tempo, usually: Allegro (fast), Largo (slow), then Allegro (fast). Each movement’s velocity is never as strictly uniform as the tempo would suggest. It’s as if velocity had been made into an atemporal category by abstracting away the velocity changes inside the movements.

Blanket concepts are a product of abstracting the medium-specific narratives into easily identifiable and well-known concepts. On the other hand, the more unique and granular the narrative, the less blanketable it becomes. For example, the aforementioned medium-specific narrative of Ode on a Grecian Urn doesn’t have (yet) a blanket term because it is fairly specific, although each step of the narrative is individually unremarkable. Some steps are a simple repetition, but are specific to the enclosing narrative. As a consequence of its specificity, the whole medium-specific narrative can only be communicated by going through all its steps in order, re-emphasizing the temporality of the structure.

Yet, blanket concepts sometimes pretend to capture uniqueness. For example, a music theory class may characterize Chopin’s music by its “question/answer structures.” The phrases played in succession on the piano almost sound like a dialogue between different instruments. But, come to think of it, one can actually say the same thing of any piece of music. It’s not only the phrases that engage into a dialogue. A phrase is divided into segments that compete to make their individual voices heard. Division is recursive and can reach down to the notes. The levels of division don’t have to be mutually exclusive; so smaller segments can enter into a dialogue with larger segments. The particular way in which a dialogue takes life is a medium-specific narrative, but the “question/answer structures” are such a broad description that they end up defeating the basic purpose of medium-specific narratives (which is to be specific).

Unique uses of repetition in medium-specific narratives cannot be described by blanket concepts. For example, William Faulkner’s A Light in August starts with a pregnant woman named Lena, on a quest to find her child’s father:

 Sitting besides the road, watching the wagon mount the hill toward her, Lena thinks, “I have come from Alabama: a fur piece. All the way from Alabama a-walking. A fur piece.”  
William Faulkner
A Light in August

The first chapter ends with the following lines:

 “My, my,” she say; “here I aint been on the road but four weeks, and now I am in Jefferson already. My, my. A body does get around.”  
William Faulkner
A Light in August

The last lines mirror the previous quotes:

 Yes, sir. You cant beat a woman. Because do you know what I think? I think she was just travelling. I dont think she had any idea of finding whoever it was she was following. I dont think she had ever aimed to, only she hadn’t told him yet. I reckon this was the first time she had ever been further away from home than she could walk back before sundown in her life. And that she had got along all right this far, with folks taking good care of her. And so I think she had just made up her mind to travel a little further and see as much as she could, since I reckon she knew that when she settled down this time, it would likely be for the rest of her life. […] after a while, I says, “Here comes Saulsbury,” and she says, “what?” and I says, “Saulsbury, Tennessee,” and I looked back and saw her face. And it was like it was already fixed and waiting to be surprised, and that she knew that when the surprise come, she was going to enjoy it. And it did come and it did suit her. Because she said, “My, my. A body does get around. Here we aint been coming from Alabama but two months, and now it’s already Tennessee.”  
William Faulkner
A Light in August

The repetition highlights two changes in particular: her destination (Tennessee instead of Jefferson) and the transition from “I have come from Alabama […] I aint been on the road but four weeks” to “we aint been coming from Alabama but two months,” as she gave birth halfway through the book. The discovery of this indifference toward the destination since the beginning of the book (“I think she was just travelling. I dont think she had any idea of finding whoever it was she was following”) recontextualizes all that happens in-between the repeated bits (so the whole book, basically), as the reader realizes that the birth did wreak havoc in the lives of all the main characters, except “we”—Lena and the baby, who get the smoothest ride of all (“she had got along all right this far, with folks taking good care of her”).

The use of repetition to highlight a detail also underlies a medium-specific narrative of Yasmina Reza’s Dans la luge d’Arthur Schopenhauer. This time, the repetition is contained in a single sentence, the last one in the book.

 A woman gets up on the right foot, she goes out, she leaves for the day on the right foot, […] when suddenly she gets slowed by the body of another woman, […] we don’t want to stand in solidarity with the woman with the bags, we want to walk fast, we want to hit the ground with a bouncing step, walk without mercy, we don’t intend to turn around until the moment we turn around to see the face, fatal mistake, […] it’s a minor turnaround, which doesn’t involve the body, even though, facing her, as I said, we must fight against a stirring of the soul, unsolicited, a violent regret for something vague […] so I pause before the window display of a shoe store before which I always pause, in this shop window there’s enough to make my mood change drastically, see, I believe in frivolity, we’re fortunate to have frivolity, frivolity saves us, I’m surprised you don’t understand the superiority that we have of being saved by frivolity, the day frivolity lets us down we die, once a man said to me, about a dress that I had an eye on, the dress can wait, can wait what, I told him, until the body can’t get dressed anymore, until it’s my turn to clutter up the street, […] seeing her get closer to the shop window I thought once she was playing on the sidewalk, she was drawing a court, she was moving the lagger on one leg, she was hopping from square to square, she was hopping from square to square in her ballooning dress…  
 Une femme se lève d’un bon pied, elle sort, elle s’en va dans la journée d’un bon pied, […] quand elle se trouve soudain empêchée par le corps d’une autre, […] nous ne voulons pas être solidaire de la femme aux sacs, nous voulons marcher vite, nous voulons attaquer le sol d’un pied bondissant, marcher sans aucune pitié, nous n’avons pas l’intention de nous retourner jusqu’au moment où nous nous retournons pour voir le visage, une erreur fatale, […] c’est un retournement mineur, qui n’engage pas le corps, bien que de face disais-je, alors que nous sommes déjà loin, il faille lutter contre une flexion de l’âme, survenue malgré soi, un regret violent dont l’objet reste flou, […] alors je m’arrête devant la vitrine du magasin de chaussures devant lequel toujours je m’arrête, dans cette vitrine il y a de quoi me faire changer radicalement d’humeur, je crois voyez-vous à la frivolité, heureusement que nous avons la frivolité, la frivolité nous sauve, je suis étonnée que vous ne compreniez pas cette supériorité que nous avons d’être sauvées par la frivolité, le jour où la frivolité nous abandonne nous mourons, une fois un homme m’a dit, à propos d’une robe que j’avais repérée, la robe peut attendre, peut attendre quoi ai-je rétorqué, que le corps soit inhabillable, que j’encombre la rue à mon tour, […] en la voyant s’approcher de la vitrine j’ai pensé un jour elle s’amusait sur le trottoir, elle dessinait une marelle, elle poussait le palet à cloche-pied, elle sautait les cases, elle sautait les cases dans sa jupe gonflée… 
Yasmina Reza
On Arthur Schopenhauer’s Sledge

The repetition in the last line makes the detail of the “ballooning dress” stand out. It is the finishing touch of a metaphor synthesizing themes developed in the previous chapters: the theme of turning around, the theme of coming back, as the old woman with the bags catches up to the relentless woman, and the “frivolity” of clothing details.

On both On Arthur Schopenhauer’s Sledge and A Light in August, repetition is used in a unique medium-specific way that eludes tropes and blanket concepts. The blatantness of repetition, especially in conjunction with the strategic placement (in the concluding lines of a chapter or the whole book), is able to attract attention to details of narratives which would easily get overlooked otherwise.

Rediscovering composite media

Intra-medium narrative versus composite media such as songs. “Medium pairing” as a value judgment versus the intra-heteromedium narrative.

The notions of medium specificity and of being intra-medium bring up the question “Which medium?” A composite medium is a combination of layers, e.g., a song can be seen as lyrics on top of an instrumental. I will use the term “heteromedium” when emphasizing this compositeness, and “intra-heteromedium” to qualify an interpretation limited to the content of a heteromedium.

To be perfectly accurate, what most would consider to be a monomedium is necessarily composite. Text has sound, syntax, semantics, structure, etc. Sound has tonality, rhythm, phrasing, texture, etc. Furthermore, not one such property can be made into a “truly” one-dimensional medium. Tonality cannot exist in a vacuum, just like color cannot exist without some sense of shape, or a line without some sense of thickness. Even so, we never pay attention to everything. It is not uncommon to ignore the lyrics in a song. Other parts of the medium may be deemed unessential depending on the listener. When listening to a heavy metal song, I will usually ignore the obligatory guitar solo every other chorus, the elaborate drum fills, redundant bass lines, etc.

Despite the fundamental heterogeneity of every medium, there has always been a sense of medium unity which has overpowered the other aspects of heteromedium interpretation. It is not uncommon to hear about how well lyrics match the music, the music the movie, the dancing the music, etc. The question as to how well the layers match is typically indicative of a value judgment. But as with all value judgments, even if there is objectivity in the match—e.g., rhythmic affinity between dance and music—the accompanying value judgment is fundamentally questionable. Nothing says that only positive affinity is necessary to make a “great” match. One could argue that happy lyrics go with dark music as a spooky combination—think porcelain doll in the dark—or as a spoof. On the other hand, dark lyrics over dark music can be of great comedic value if taken too seriously, for example satanic music in a world where Christianity has become irrelevant. What is taken seriously by some is easily derided by others. The song Black Sabbath may be taken seriously by “true heavy metal” fans and Satan-fearing parents, while others laugh off the cheesy horror lyrics. The fundamental separation between the evil theme and metal music is such that people could invent the genre of “white metal,” i.e., Christ-hailing metal. In any case, celebrating evil or god in songs is and has always been as deridable as the average self-proclaimed black metal misanthropes touring the world to party with their fans while promoting their latest album.

The act of viewing a medium as a composite medium for the purposes of value judgments, “medium pairing,” is not to be mistaken with the interpretation of a heteromedium-specific narrative. Narratives are about change, which statements on fitness for purpose (“the costumes fit the medieval fantasy theme so well!”) are not. So when one talks of “medium-specific narrative,” one considers changes across the medium pairing, not the pairing itself. Typically, the medium-specific narrative of a song (to mind: not album, not artist, but the individual song itself) focuses on melody, not style, genre, technique, or production (all invariants with respect to the narrative), and only deals with harmony insofar it partakes in producing melody. The purely musical narrative is usually tangent to the lyrics, although one can always try to look for narratives from the coupling of music with lyrics (rather than the meaning of music in lyrics, or the meaning of music in emotion), just like comics combine drawings and text into a particular type of narrative material, as was seen with Touti and his Exhaust Pipe.